A version of this article appears in:

 

 

Transformative Motherhood: On Giving and Getting in a Consumer Culture. Linda Layne, ed. New York: New York University Press. 2000.

 

 


 

 

 

 

The Gift of Life: Surrogate Motherhood, Gamete Donation and Constructions of Altruism

 

 

 

 

Blessed are those who can give without remembering,

 and take without forgetting.

 

                                                                                                --Princess Elizabeth Asquith Bibesco

 

 

 

 

 

          In the anthropological literature, one of the first systematic and

 

comparative studies on the cultural significance of gift giving was Mauss’s

 

The Gift. As Mauss so eloquently said:

 

          Things have values which are emotional

          as well as material; indeed in some cases

          the values are entirely emotional (Mauss 1967:63).

Mauss’s assessment of gifts is not dissimilar to that of Levi Strauss who has also written:

          Goods are not only economic commodities

          but vehicles and instruments for realities of

          another order: influence, power, sympathy,

          status, emotion ... (Levi Strauss 1965:262).

          In American culture, a culture in which commercialization penetrates nearly all domains, one cannot help but be struck by the widely varied uses to which the “gift of life” theme has been applied. The cultural significance of the gift theme resides in its ability to provide both a literal and a symbolic counterpoint to the increasing commodification of modern life. While many anthropologists have studied the significance of the gift, it is interesting that  the gift for the most part remains understudied in industrial capitalist society (Carrier 1990). Traditionally, in American culture, the gift’s application has been confined (almost entirely) to the arenas of blood donation and organ donation where it has been “lavishly applied” (Fox and Swazey 1992:44). The inclusion of organ donation and blood donation under the rubric of “gift” may be an attempt by participants and by society to retard, at least symbolically, the trend toward the commodification of life.{1}

          My own interest in the cultural resonance of the gift of life theme came about somewhat circuitously as I was conducting research on surrogate motherhood. During the course of that research, I discovered that surrogate mothers often conceptualize the child/children they are producing for commissioning couples as a “gift of life” and/or as “gifts.” This they do in spite of the fact that they are compensated for their reproductive act.

          With traditional surrogacy (in which the surrogate contributes an ovum), both surrogates and commissioning couples routinely refer to the children born of these arrangements as gifts. This practice can be understood as related to EuroAmerican kinship ideology, in particular its emphasis upon the importance of biogenetic relatedness. Perhaps not surprisingly, I have also discovered that with gestational surrogacy, where the surrogate gestates the couples’ embryos, noticeably less “gifting language” is utilized to describe these children, an issue that I will address in greater depth in a later section of this chapter.

          The gift of life theme, when applied to traditional surrogate motherhood, reveals the ways in which issues such as work, indebtedness, pricelessness, family, and kinship are being reconfigured. In this chapter, I would like to explore the multivariant meanings attaching to the gift theme in the context of traditional surrogacy, gestational surrogacy and gamete donation. I would also like to explore how the gift of life theme serves as powerful reinforcement for EuroAmerican kinship ideology and speaks (at least in the context of traditional surrogacy) to the inviolability of the blood tie.

 

Methods

          Data for this chapter is the result of nine years of ongoing ethnographic research. Twenty-six formal interviews of gestational surrogates were conducted, as well as twelve interviews with individual members of couples (i.e., individuals who had enlisted the services of gestational surrogates), in addition to five ovum donors. Although several of the individuals I interviewed are/were clients at the largest surrogate mother and ovum donation program in the world, several were not. I also intentionally sought to interview couples who had advertised for and screened their own gestational surrogates rather than contracting with a program in order to compare their experiences against those of couples enrolled in programs. In addition to these formal interviews I was able to observe numerous consultations between program staff, intending couples and prospective surrogate mothers, as well as, conducting thousands of hours of participant observation. I have attempted, whenever possible, to select individuals from the various phases of the gestational surrogacy and ovum donation process, e.g., individuals who have not yet been matched, who are newly matched and who are attempting “to get pregnant,” who have confirmed pregnancies, who have recently given birth, as well as individuals for whom several years have elapsed since the birth of their child. My decision to interview individuals in all stages of the process has been to assess what, if any shifts individuals might experience as they go through the process.

 

Background

          When I began my research on surrogate motherhood in 1988, gestational (IVF) surrogacy was a relatively uncommon procedure. Surrogate motherhood arrangements required that the surrogate contribute an ovum to the creation of the child and be inseminated with the intending father’s semen. However, during the six-year period that followed, the practice of gestational surrogacy increased in the United States at a rather remarkable rate, from less than 5 percent of all surrogate arrangements to approximately 50 percent as of 1994 (Ragoné 1994;1998). With gestational surrogacy, the surrogate does not contribute an ovum, but insteads “gestates” a couple’s embryo(s); and for this reason, gestational surrogates in general tend to begin the process with different concerns and expectations than traditional surrogates. But not all gestational surrogate arrangements involve the couples’ embryos; numerous cases involve the use of donor ova and the intending father’s semen. The question is why do couples (who use donor ova) pursue gestational surrogacy when traditional surrogacy can provide them with the same degree of biogenetic linkage/relatedness to the child and has a higher likelihood of being successful. It also costs significantly less. Typically, several reasons are cited by the largest surrogate mother program which is now also the largest ovum donation program in the U.S. with over 300 screened donors on file. The primary reason is consumer choice, specifically that couples who choose the donor ova/gestational surrogacy route rather then traditional surrogacy have a significantly greater number of ovum donors to choose from than they have traditional surrogates. But, of equal importance is that when commissioning couples choose donor ova/gestational surrogacy they are severing the surrogates’ genetic link to and/or claim to the child, whereas with traditional surrogacy the adoptive mother must emphasize the importance of nurturance and social parenthood, while the surrogate deemphasizes her biogenetic tie to the child.

 

Remunerating the Gift

          Thus far, the image of surrogate mothers has been shaped principally by media, legal, and scholarly portrayals of surrogates either as motivated principally by monetary gain or as unwitting, altruistic victims of the patriarchy. This tendency to cast surrogates’ motivations into either/or, often antagonistic categories may reveal a great deal more about EuroAmerican culture than it does about surrogacy itself.

          Surrogates readily acknowledge that remuneration was one of their initial considerations, although they consistently deny that it was their primary motivation (and nearly all surrogates state--repeatedly--that the importance of remuneration decreased over time).{2} When questioned about remuneration, surrogates consistently protest that no one would become a surrogate for the money alone because, they reason, it simply “isn’t enough.” Many surrogate program directors report that surrogates telephone their programs unaware that payment is involved, a phenomenon that would seem to reinforce surrogates’ claims that remuneration is not their primary motivation. As Jan Sutton, founder and spokeswoman for a group of surrogates in favor of surrogacy, stated in her testimony before an information-gathering committee to the California state legislature, “My organization and its members would all still be surrogates if no payment were involved,” a sentiment not unrepresentative of those expressed by the many surrogates I have interviewed over the years.{3} Interestingly enough, after Sutton had informed the committee of that fact, several members of the panel who had previously voiced their opposition to surrogacy in its commerical form began to express praise for Sutton, indicating that her testimony had altered their opinion of surrogacy. In direct response to her testimony, the committee began instead to discuss a proposal to ban commerical surrogacy but to allow for the practice of noncommercial surrogacy (in which a surrogate is barred from receiving financial compensation, although the physicians and lawyers involved are allowed their usual compensation for services rendered, as in organ donation). This perceptual shift on the part of committee members can be understood to result from an overriding cultural imperative that motherhood, reproduction and family be squarely situated in a noncommercial sphere, a position which also explains why these same committee members saw no inconsistency in permitting “professionals,” i.e., physicians and attorneys, to receive compensation for services rendered. 

          The following are typical surrogate responses to questions about how payment influenced their decision to become a surrogate: 

          It sounded so interesting and fun. The

          money wasn’t enough to be pregnant

          for nine months,

and:

          I’m not doing it for the money. Take

          the money. That wouldn’t stop me.

          It wouldn’t stop the majority.

and again:

          What’s $10,000 bucks? You can’t even

          buy a car . . . . Money wasn’t important.

          I possibly would have done it just for

          expenses, especially for the people I did

          it for. My father would have given me

          the money not to do it.

Surrogates’ devaluation of payment as insufficient to compensate for “nine months of pregnancy” can be understood to fulfill two functions. It is, of course, representative of the cultural belief that children are “priceless” (Zelizer 1985), and in this sense, surrogates are merely reiterating a widely-held belief when they devalue the remuneration they receive. But their devaluation also serves as evidence that the perfect gift is one that is priceless, one that transcends “material expression and economic worth” and that renders the material immaterial (Carrier 1990: 23).{4}

          Interestingly enough, when the largest surrogate mother program changed its newspaper advertisements from “Help an Infertile Couple” to “Give the Gift of Life,” the new formula attracted the type of woman the program wished to attract and the program received a considerably larger volume of response from suitable prospective surrogates.{5} The ad struck a chord with surrogates because it acknowledged that their act is one that can not be compensated for monetarily; instead, it cast surrogacy in a poignant and life-affirming light, more clearly locating it in the gift economy. The above example reveals the highly gendered nature of the gift; falling as it does unequivocally within the female domain be it surrogates, and ovum donors, but interestingly enough not with sperm donors.

           Surrogates’ dismissal of the importance of remuneration also serves an underlying function, as reflected in the following quotes. Here, a surrogate who had earlier dismissed the importance of money, offers a more revealing account of her decision to become a surrogate mother:

          I wanted to do the ultimate thing for somebody,

          to give them the ultimate gift. Nobody can beat

          that, nobody can do anything nicer for them.

Another surrogate, who also used the word “ultimate,” discussed her feelings about surrogacy in a similar way:

          It’s a gift of love. I have always been

          a really giving person, and it’s the

          ultimate way to give. I’ve always had

          babies so easily. It’s the ultimate gift of love.

Another surrogate echoed the gift theme:

          They [the couple] consider it [the baby]

          a gift and I consider it a gift.

And here, a surrogate who initially opposed AI surrogacy explained her decision in this way:

          I wasn’t using those eggs every month and

          I realized they didn’t mean as much to me

          as I thought they did. It was like giving an

          extra gift to the couple, one extra part

          of me.

We can surmise that when this surrogate used the word “extra” to describe the gift, she did so as a means to underscore the extraordinary nature of the gift. Another surrogate critiqued the very notion of associating the child with a dollar value when she said: “You can’t put a price on a baby’s life.”

          The gift formulation holds particular appeal for surrogates because it reinforces the idea that having a child for someone is an act that cannot be compensated; the gift of life narrative is further enhanced by some surrogates to embrace the near-sacrifice of their own lives in child birth.{6} Thus, when surrogates define the children they are reproducing for couples as “gifts,” they are tacitly suggesting that no amount of money would ever provide sufficient compensation. Distributive justice (Schwartz 1967) cannot be attained in the traditional surrogacy arrangement. The child as a gift clearly approaches the highest ideals of gift giving since it fulfils the criteria for the perfect gift.

          For EuroAmericans it is  “gift relations” rather than economic exchanges that characterize the family (Carrier 1990:2). Thus, when surrogates minimize or dismiss the importance of money, they are on the one hand reiterating cultural beliefs about the pricelessness of children, and they are on the other hand suggesting that the exchange of a child for money is not a relationship of reciprocity but of kinship.

          With traditional surrogacy, the relationship is, as with adoption (Modell 1999: this volume) one of indebtedness. Even though surrogates are discouraged from thinking of their relationship to the couple as a permanent one, surrogates recognize that they are creating a state of enduring solidarity between themselves and their couples. This belief complicates the severing of that relationship once the child has been born even though the surrogate knows in advance that the surrogate-couple relationship is structured to be impermanent.

          Surrogates’ framing of the equation as one in which a gift is given thus serves as a reminder to their couples that one of the symbolic functions of money, namely, the “removal of the personal element from human relationships through its indifferent and objective nature” (Simmel 1978:297), may be insufficient to erase certain relationships, and that the relational element may continue to surface despite the monetary exchange.

          Of all the surrogates’ motivations, remuneration is the most problematic. On a symbolic level, of course, remuneration detracts from the idealized cultural image of women/mothers as selfless, nurturant and altruistic, an image that surrogates do not wish to lose; in addition, if surrogates were to acknowledge the money as a fair and equal exchange or sufficient compensation for their reproductive work, they would lose the sense that theirs is a gift that cannot be compensated for monetarily.

          In Britain, where commercial surrogacy was outlawed in 1985 with the passage of the Surrogacy Arrangements Bill (Wolfram 1987:189), the situation has been framed in moral terms:

          The symbol of the ‘pure’ surrogate who creates

          a child for love was pitted against the symbol

          of the ‘wicked’ surrogate who prostitutes her

          maternity (Cannell 1990:683).

The idea of ‘pure’ versus ‘wicked’ surrogacy and, correspondingly, good versus bad surrogates, is predicated on the belief that altruism precludes remuneration. The overwhelming acceptance of the idea of unpaid or noncommercial surrogacy (both in the United States and abroad) can be attributed to the fact that it “duplicates maternity in culturally the most self-less manner” (Strathern 1991:31). But perhaps even more important, the rejection of paid or commercial surrogacy may also result from a cultural resistance to conflating the symbolic value of the family with the world of work to which it has long been held in opposition. Drawing together those two spheres is the agency of the surrogate who bridges them through her reproductive work. In the Baby M case, for example, the most “decisive issue” was one of “payment to the surrogate” (Hull 1990b:155). As David Schneider so succinctly described the equation, “what is done is done for love, not for money. And it is love, of course, that money can’t buy” (Schneider 1968:45).

This truth is reflected in one father’s remarks about his surrogate:

          I realize now that what Jane [the surrogate] gave

          was a part of herself; that’s fairly profound.

Thus, the child serves as a point of connection between the surrogate and the father in the same way that it does between the wife and husband. When Swartz pointed out in 1967 that “the gift imposes an identity upon the giver as well as the receiver” (Swartz 1967:2) he could not have envisioned the literalization of this idea through surrogacy. By acknowledging that the surrogate child is a gift, the couple accepts a permanent state of indebtedness to their surrogate. The quote cited above, in which the father refers to the surrogate giving part of herself, also reflects the enduring quality of the blood tie, a relationship that can never be severed in American kinship ideology. This is because, as Schneider noted, blood is “culturally defined as being an objective fact of nature” (Schneider 1968:24). It is therefore impossible for a person to have an ex-blood relative, e.g., an ex-mother, ex-father, or ex-sibling (Schneider 1968:24). In addition to the fact that blood is understood to be “a shared bodily substance,” there is also the “connection between ideas of blood ... and ideas of genes” (Strathern and Franklin 1993:20). Fathers cannot help but acknowledge this connection and comment upon it, and neither can surrogates and adoptive mothers.{5}

          Because all gift giving creates a degree of gratitude, when couples bestow additional gifts{6} upon their surrogates (as they do from the moment the pregnancy is confirmed, to the moment the child is born and even after), they, like their surrogate, enter into a gift economy. Gifts are given with such regularity and predictability by couples to their surrogates (and to her children as well) that such acts have become encouraged by surrogate programs. However, the actual birth of the child and the surrogate’s relinquishment of the child to the couple is viewed by all participants as the embodiment of the penultimate act of giving/gifting. It is therefore of interest that couples routinely bestow upon their surrogates gifts of jewelry that prominently feature the child’s birthstone, a gift that (unlike impermanent gifts, e.g., vacations and dinners) commemoratively embodies the birth of the child. As Layne (1999) in her study of pregnancy loss narratives, reveals “memorial jewelry” specifically “mother’s rings” which contain the child’s birth stone are often bestowed upon the mother of a child lost through miscarriage or stillbirths as an undying symbol of the child. While Layne’s work explores the utilization of goods/gifts in the context of pregnancy loss, memorializing a child after her/his death can also be extended to the gifts of jewlery bestowed upon surrogates. Specifically, jewlery which contains the child’s birth stone memorializes the surrogate child for the surrogate and, it might be argued that a surrogate child is for many surrogates constructed in such a way as to also be symbolically deceased. Such a gift represents an acknowledgement that expensive, impermanent gifts such as vacations are mere tokens of appreciation that cannot repay the extraordinary generosity of the surrogate, and here the earlier surrogate comment “you cannot put a price on a child” is apropos.

          In this way, gifts of precious and semi-precious stones are intended to transcend the lives of givers and receivers. In the case of surrogacy they are  a particularly suitable gift since such stones attempt to acknowledge the permanent connection that prevails between surrogate and child and surrogate and father both of which bespeak the inviolability of the blood tie in EuroAmerican kinship ideology. Of critical importance for surrogates is their ability to describe the child as a gift, a description which serves as validation for their reproductive work. But perhaps of even greater importance, the gift formulation acknowledges their unique contribution toward the creation of a family, an act that cannot (and in the view of many participants, should not) be reduced to mere commodification. This perspective also prevails in the world of adoption where the language utilized by participants emphasizes the “gift, giving, and generosity” (Modell p. 11 this volume) and ultimately softens the idea that adoption creates a “market for babies” (Modell 1999:11).

          But surrogates and couples also recognize, at least tacitly, that true distributive justice cannot be achieved since such justice is only possible in pure economic exchanges. It does not occur in social exchanges that involve relationships (Swartz 1967:8), and certainly not in those that involve the gift of life. As Fox and Swazey pointed out in their research on organ donation, it is not unusual for organ recipients to feel a “sense of obligation” due to the extraordinary nature of the gift proffered. Like an organ, a child is a gift exchange that is “inherently unreciprocal” since it does not have a “physical or symbolic equivalent” (Fox and Swazey 1992:40).

 

Commodifying Gestational Surrogacy and Gamete Donation

          The children produced through traditional surrogacy arrangements tend to be viewed by all parties through the gift lens, a formulation that explicitly rests upon the shared acknowledgement that what the surrogate gives is literally a part of herself.{7} However, a shift has occurred as gestational surrogacy supercedes traditional [which involves either the implantation of the couple’s embryos or donor ova and husband’s/partner’s semen into a gestational surrogate], specifically, this gift rhetoric is notably underused. One probable explanation is the influence of the hegemonic biogenetic model of kinship. The explicit articulation of relatedness reveals the tendency on the part of commissioning couples to view themselves as “ending up with exactly the same child that they would have ended up if it were not for the wife/woman’s inability to carry a pregnancy to term,” as one resident psychologist explained to me.

          Her assessment demonstrates that with gestational surrogacy there is a tendency, perhaps a logical one, for couples to place less emphasis upon the role and/or contribution of their surrogate and more emphasis on the outcome. Because she does not contribute an ovum, or a “piece of herself,” the surrogate’s role is increasingly seen by some participants as that of “vessel” or “vehicle,”{8} as reflected in couples’ language. For example, one 36-year -old father offered the following assessment concerning the role of his gestational surrogate and her relationship to him, his wife, and the child:

          I don’t think about it much. She was an oven . . . .

          she doesn’t see herself as the mother. We

          don’t see her as the mother and that’s the way

          it is [emphasis added].{9}

          With gestational surrogacy, commissioning couples place less emphasis on the children as gifts and greater emphasis on the processural component of reproduction than do AI couples. When I discussed my theory about the absence of gift rhetoric with the director of the largest surrogate mother program, she confirmed my observations. She had observed, for example, that IVF (gestational) surrogacy couples, are in her experience, “more difficult” and “less kind at the birth and soon after the birth” to their surrogates. Typically, for example, surrogates want their own children to see and/or hold the child/children shortly after they are born. This practice is intended to provide the surrogate’s children (and the surrogates themselves) with closure, and it is encouraged by the program and its psychologists. And here again, this director observed that the only time “I have had couples run out of a hospital [with the baby] is IVF couples. AI couples will stay around for 10 days [after the birth of the child and her/his discharge from the hospital].” AI couples, on the other hand, the director noted, “want the [surrogate’s] children to hold the babies.” By way of explanation, many IVF couples say that they do not want anyone holding their children because they fear contagion or “germs.” But the director’s observation were that these couples appear to feel that a surrogate’s children “have the right” to hold their infants and they “almost behave like a stranger situation.”

          Even when the pregnancy produces a multiple birth, a fairly common phenomenon, a situation that might be expected to produce a heightened sense of gratitude in couples, the director had observed that they are actually less “kind” to their surrogate than when a “singleton” (one child) is born. The center’s contract states that for every additional child couples must pay an additional $3,000 and, according to the director’s assessment, a new pattern is emerging in which couples who have twins or triplets tend to give their surrogates smaller gifts. Couples frequently propose to give expensive gifts to their surrogate but very few IVF couples who receive multiple children keep this promise, and it appears (at least initially) that surrogates who give birth to singletons receive more gifts. How do we account for this behavior? The program director’s theory is that because a multiple birth means that a couple’s family is complete and will no longer require the surrogate’s services (or the program’s services), such couples therefore “don’t care what the we think of them either,” often flouting program directives concerning appropriate behavior toward their surrogate.

 

Ovum Donation: Where Have all the Gifts Gone?

          My interest in gamete donation was generated by the intersection of ovum donation with gestational surrogacy. The largest surrogate mother program is also the world’s largest ovum donation program. Intending couples who are unable to produce their own embryos have the option of choosing from over 300 screened ovum donors at the surrogate program. It should be noted that what constitutes relatedness in one context and appears to be consistent with EuroAmerican kinship ideology is, however, inconsistent in other contexts, most notably with gamete donation.    

          Interestingly, gamete donation programs/clinics/banks intentionally seek to separate gametes from their donors in ways that bear a striking similarity to adoption practices. Like adoption, gamete donation (both ovum or sperm donation) “arose out of market concerns; an imbalance between supply and demand, a scarcity of the desired product ...” (Modell 1999:6 this volume.), and it was the routinization and naturalization of IVF that resulted in an increased demand for ova. Intense competition among infertility clinics and the prospect of enormous profits coupled with weak regulatory policies (Reame 1998:1) has created a volatile environment. Although a great deal has been written about the practice of inflating their “success rates,” at infertility clinics little has been written about the common practice of advertising for ova donors in college newspapers. Acting on the questionable assumption that women in college possess the genetic potential to produce more intelligent children, clinics seek ova from a cohort known to be in need of financial compensation by using financial incentives (just as sperm banks do). It is interesting to note that while gamete donation programs/banks only accept donations from individuals who are either currently enrolled in college (or who are college graduates) no such emphasis exists in the field of blood or organ donation. In an attempt to recruit college-aged women, advertisements for ova donors have changed their rates from a $2,500 payment for one cycle to a single, larger sum of $10,000 (for 3-4 cycles), a sum of money that is more attractive. These ads do not indicate, however, the number of cycles involved in the larger payment, intending to draw in candidates through the appeal of a lump sum payment. Ovum “donation” then, like sperm “donation,” is explicitly predicated on a remunerative model, it may appear to be outside the province of gifting, but it is not. 

          The idea of altruism in the context of gamete donation, in particular ovum donation provides a particularly interesting and vital link to an understanding of the complexity of the gift. As we will see gift rhetoric is not only contextually dependent, it is also highly gendered.

 

Gendering the Gift

          Gender in the world of assisted conception is a crucial, if curiously understudied variable, particularly with respect to men and gamete donation. For example, studies on sperm donation have revealed that: 71% of sperm donors are motivated by the following factors: remuneration (Schover et al., 1992), a desire to assess their own fertility (Handelsman et al., 1985; Daniels 1989), altruism (Handelsman et al., 1985; Daniels 1989; Schover et al., 1992) and, interestingly enough, outcomes, i.e., donors are interested in knowing whether children were born from their donation (Handelsman et al., 1985; Daniels 1989; Mahlstedt and Probasco 1991; Purdie et al., 1994; Schover et al., 1992). Before a donor is accepted his semen is accessed for motility, sperm count, and so on which allows a donor to assess his fertility. These test results are different from those that inform donors about the actual number of  births that have occurred as a result of their act of donation.) 

          Given a cultural model that equates good morther with nurturance and altruism, ovum donors are less likely than sperm donors to acknowledge the importance of remuneration. The dictates of this cultural model are mirrored by sperm banks and ovum donation program staff. Clinicians, for example, are “highly influential” in “creating the overall atmosphere  . . . in which donors and recipients experience gamete donation,” (Hamies 1993:1518) as revealed in a study conducted by the University of Southern California’s oocyte donation program. Clinicians Sauer and Paulson reveal that as part of the screening process for prospective ovum donors the USC program insists that the “primary reason for participation . . .  [be] a desire to help an infertile woman have a baby” (Sauer and Paulson 1992:727). In spite of this policy, which is intended to screen out women who express financial incentive, 76% of the women who had completed “at least one aspiration stated that compensation was important for their continued participation” (Sauer and Paulson 1992:727).

          Why then are women who express some financial motivation turned away in spite of the fact that approved donors, once accepted, subsequently reveal that remuneration is important to them? And why are sperm donors, who routinely state the importance of financial compensation, accepted?  Sauer and Paulson’s conclusion was that “oocyte donors represent a rather unique group of individuals. . . . very different from men donating to our sperm bank” (Sauer and Paulson 1992:726), a conclusion that is questionable in view of the fact that 76% of that program’s screened and accepted ovum donors appear to value compensation as do 71% of all sperm donors. Such assessments regrettably conflate commonly accepted, essentialist notions about gender, selectively reinforcing ideas of  “altruism” and “gifting” only as they pertain to women.

          The irony of programs using financial incentive to attract ovum donors and then requiring them to deemphasise its importance reveals a deepseated ambivalence in EuroAmerican culture about commercializing, commodifying, and fragmenting both the body and the family. And ovum donors are the first to reflect this ambivalence. As one 28-year-old ovum donor’s unsolicited explanation illustrates, “Whatever money I acquired I would use in some way to better my children’s life.”  Another ovum donor felt that her donation needed an explanation,, “I got brownie points somewhere.” As these remarks reveal, it is not uncommon for ovum donors to indirectly apologize for or somehow excuse their having accepted compensation for their reproductive work. Responses such as these harken back to the script-like quality responses I received from traditional surrogates to deemphasize the remunerative component and to foreground ideas consistent with feminine/maternal behavior, such as altruism, caring, and sharing (Ragoné 1994; 1996); such responses can be understood to reflect the tension between market driven forces that set the price on how much an infertility clinic can compensate a donor for her ova and the altruistic component of donors’ acts. One 24-year-old donor provided a fairly explicit synopsis of this cultural tension when she said:

          I was worried what people would think

          of me. A close friend made a snide comment

           about me selling off parts of myself. It made

           me feel like it was a trashy kind of thing to do.

          What kind of women would do it? Then it became,

          ‘I am the kind of women who would do this!’

           Specifically, when programs insist upon anonymity, i.e., minimal or no contact between ovum donor and intending couple, they tend to reinforce the idea that gamete donation is a quid pro quo exchange, i.e., donors receive payment and couples receive gametes. But although psychological studies indicate that the anonymous model is not ideal, most programs respond the the wishes of their paying clients (Baran and Pannor 1989). As the director of the world largest sperm bank informed me, in spite of his own psychological staff informing him of the importance of abolishing anonymity and moving the bank into a more interactive and open model, there are currently no plans to implement this since he reasoned it is not what his clients. The belief that children’s psychological response is healthier when they are informed of their birth origins, that secrecy in the family should be discouraged, and that infertile individuals must come to terms with their infertility are the primary reasons that psychologists recommend more interactive open models be implemented for donation. 

          Anonymous models of donation appear to have produced negative consequences for some donors as revealed by a 28-year-old ovum donor whose first donation [facilitated by a private physician] was completely anonymous. She described her experience as an emotionally difficult one:

          It made me feel like a prostitute.

          It was disgusting. I left there crying.

          In the end, I said, ‘I will never do this

          again.’ It was a horrible experience. 

However, she went on to donate two additional times in a program that encouraged open communication between ova donors and recipient couples/individuals. One of the psychologists at the program she chose described the donor’s decision to donate again in an open program as one that “help[ed] her to heal.” In this case, participating in an open donation program appears to have accorded the donor a greater degreee of agency and to have placed her act of donation into the gift economy. 

          The decision of many clinics to retain the anonymity model in spite of evidence that it is not necessarily in the best interest of donors or children  has produced an untenable situation for many ovum donors since they are required, on the one hand, to view their donation as altruistic, an aspect of the gift model, but on the other hand, because they will never have contact with the couples or women who receive their ova the relationship resembles an economic arrangement. The previously quoted donor who reported feeling that she had “prostituted” herself, and the other who felt that she was “selling body parts,” were expressing feelings remarkably similar to those expressed to me by surrogates participating in anonymous programs, namely that the process served to produce feelings of fragmentation of self.    

          Anonymity facilitates the denial of the genetic component of donation for both donors and recipients and permits recipient couples to deny their infertility. The following quote by a 32-year-old, however, reveals the confusion faciliated by an anonymous model that seeks to ignore issues of relatedness,  

          I thought ‘wow, my eggs are going

          to be a child.’ I don’t consider it my

          child. It is in a way my child. It was a

          weird feeling. Donating eggs is much

          different than being face to face with

          what you donated. I don’t think of them

          as related to me.

Although this donor later added, “It’s a good feeling helping someone have a baby,” it is not uncommon for ovum donors to ignore the link between ova and children. This conceptual gap is the byproduct of both anonymity and commodification.{10}

          One 33-year-old ovum donor explained her view of the separation between her ova and the potential child in this way, creating a self and other distinction based on that which is inside the body and that which is outside the body,

          It [the baby] really isn’t mine even though

          they [the ova] are mine. Once it’s not in me,

          I don’t consider it mine. [Italics added]

          Her statement echoes the perception embraced by most gestational surrogates, specifically, that the children are not theirs because they do not have any “genetic” connection to the children they produce. The difference, however, between gestational surrogates and ovum donors is that ovum donors are in fact genetically linked to these children, whereas gestational surrogates are not.{11} But what is of fundamental importance is that various versions as to what does or does not constitute relatedness in EuroAmerican kinship ideology co-exist and their co-existence has a great deal to do with the fragmentation and commodification of the body, as illustrated by the following quote by 28-year-old donor mentioned earlier who analogized her donation experience to that of prostites. Placing her gift in context, she added the following:

          I compare it [ovum donation] to donating

          blood, platelets or bone marrow. You aren’t

            giving life, but you are saving life. [Emphasis added]

Her statment can be understood as an attempt to reconceptualize her act of donation and to provide a more finely textured, albeit unclear, theory about life, i.e., “giving life” we are informed cannot be understood as the equivalent of “saving life,” a distinction which reveals the deepseated ambivalence some ovum donors experience. One psychologist who routinely screens ovum donors informed me that ovum donors often equate their donation with blood, organ and bone marrow transplantations, an analogy that is intended to include their act of donation in the gift economy. One particularly astute 24- year-old donor described her experience of trying to separate herself from her ova and the potential child in the following way,

          I was concerned I would have an emotional

          attachment to the baby. I was concerned down

          the road if I was the biological mother. If the child

          wanted to meet you  . . .  it would be cruel not to. It is

          something I don’t think about a lot. Keeping up that

          line in my mind I knew that the one thing I had to do

          was keep an emotional distance in myself . . . I knew I

          had [to] for my own sanity, I had to do it. I had to draw the

          line in the sand because I cannot risk an emotional

          attachment.

          The attempt at emotional distancing and the figurative act of “drawing a line in the sand” to separate herself from the child(ren) a donation might produce represents both an explicit acknowledgement of the biogenetic tie and an attempt to deny that connection. In another study that examines the experiences of recipient couples at The Center for Reproductive Medicine and Inferility at Cornell University Medical College, Applegarth, et al., inform us that 90% of couples in their program use anonymous donation while another 9.7%  use “known” donation, e.g., biological sister donation (Applegarth, et al., 1995:576). The authors concluded that only a “small percentage,” 10% of husbands and 26% of wives, “expressed the desire to meet their ovum donor” (Applegarth, et al., 1995:577), but the fact that more than one-quarter of the women wanted to meet their donors seems significant, especially in a program where such meetings are in all likelihood discouraged. It is also impossible to ascertain whether the following remarks attributed to several recipient women are typical. According to Applegarth et al., recipents offer thanks for their ovum donation in the following order: to “God,” “the wonders of modern medical miracles,” and “fantastic technology.” Only one of the recipients had expressed thanks to her donor (Applegarth, et al., 1995:580).

          The attempt by programs and clinicians to argue that anonymity is an acceptable strategy may be understood as an attempt to privilege the desires of paying clients, i.e., the recipient couple, a practice that has a long history in the annals of sperm donation. It is disconcerting that, due to the anonymity model, individuals who are able to have children through gamete donation do not feel the same sense of indebtedness to their donors as do those who participate in traditional surrogacy. As we have seen, the practice of anonymity in both ovum donation programs and sperm banks contributes to the further fragmentation of reproduction and the body, a fragmentation that is inextricably connected to the desire to maintain the commodification model.   

 

Conclusion

          An exploration of the gift in the context of surrogate motherhood and gamete donation illuminates the many and contradictory tensions that the commodification of life produces, from a resistance to conflating the symbolic value of family with work, on the one hand, to a desire to justify and even embrace the commodification of life on the other. With surrogacy, as with gamete donation, the enduring power of EuroAmerican kinship ideology continues to surface in spite of concerted attempts to obscure it. As one surrogate program director stated, in the course of discussing the New Jersey Supreme Court’s ruling that surrogacy represents a form of baby selling in the Baby M Case, “How can a father buy his own child?  He can’t!”

          Whether it is used in surrogate motherhood or gamete donation, gift exchange is, as Malinowski noted, “one of the main instruments of social organization” (Malinowski 1922:167). It sheds light on the quality and value of human relationships (Titmus 1971:13), and the multivariant forms that the gift of life takes will undoubtedly continue to puzzle and in some respects confound us, as technology continues to raise previously unimaginable questions.

 


End Notes

1. However, it is important to bear in mind that in spite of the heavy symbolic load associated with the gift of life 35% of all blood donors in the United States were paid for their donation until 1964 (Titmuss 1971: 93), and this practice which attracts “alcoholics and other unfortunates who return frequently to blood banks” (Titmuss 1971:114). Remuneration is a critically important issue since many blood donors are aware that “they will be deprived of money if they answer yes to questions about jaundice, malaria, and other infectious diseases” (Titums 1971: 114). It is clear that the practice has affected the safety of our blood supply; and experts have concluded that blood received from noncommerical banks is categorically safer than blood obtained from commerical banks (Titmuss 1971: 152). Profit also permeates the field of organ donation and it has resulted in the argument that a donor’s family is entitled to compensation (reference) (for their loss, act of generosity, and because all the other parties involved benefit, e.g., the recipient, transplantation teams, hospitals, and so on), a position to which I have expressed strong opposition (Ragoné 1996).

 2. The version frequently put forth by surrogate mother programs is that the importance of money decreases as the pregnancy progresses.

  3. Since 1988 I have formally interviewed 30 traditional surrogates and 25 gestational surrogates, and I have also had countless informal conversation with surrogates.

4. This tendency to deemphasize remuneration has also been found among Norwegian teenage baby-sitters (known as passepike, or girls who “look after” children). Marianne Gullestad reports that even though remuneration is important to these girls, they share in a cultural ideology that devalues the importance of payment for such a service. For this reason, when asked, the girls say that “they do not look after children for the sake of money, but because they are fond of children (er glad I barn)” (Gullestad 1992:119).

 5. The program had changed its advertising copy due to the fact that the newspaper refused to print an ad that explicitly sought a woman to serve as a surrogate. This policy has since changed.

 6. Surrogates frequently discuss their feelings concerning difficult pregnancies and deliveries in terms that suggest “heroic suffering” and “heroism” (Ragone’ 1994, 1996).

7. Interestingly enough, in other contexts, all parties intentionally deemphasize this contribution (Ragoné 1994; 1996).

8. Tentatively, I would suggest that this appears to be especially true when couples have located their gestational surrogate independently rather than through a program since they do not receive any guidance about appropriate behavior. 

9. When this husband’s wife telephoned me one year later (for information unrelated to our interview) she apologized for the way her husband had spoken of their surrogate, assuring me that he no longer felt that way although she did not provide specific details of, glossing over his comments and seeming embarrassed by them.

10. Even in anonymous programs, it is not unusual for donors to inquire about the outcomes of their donation. Some programs do inform donors as to whether or not their donation resulted in children. Some also provide information about the gender of the child, while others will not.

11. Fathers it should be noted who have participated in traditonal surrogacy also tend to downplay the significance of their genetic relationship to the child by foregoing the paternity test (Ragoné 1994; 1996).


References Cited

 

Applegarth, L., Goldberg, N., Cholst, I., McGoff, N., Fantini, D., Zeller, N.,           Black, A., and Rosenwaks, Z.

1995          Families Created Through Ovum Donation: A Preliminary                       Investigation of Obstetrical Outcome and Psychosocial                                      Adjustment. Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 12                     (9): 574-580.

 

Baran, Annette and Pannor, Reuben

1989  Lethal Secrets: The Psychology of Donor Insemination. New                              York: Amistad Press.

 

Barratt, C.L., Chauhan, M. and Cooke, I.D.

1990 Donor Insemination--A Look to the Future. Fertility and Sterility                  54: 375-387.

 

Cannell, Fenella

  1990 Concepts of Parenthood: The Warnock Report, the Gillick and                       Modern Debates. American Ethnologist 17:667-686.

 

Carrier, James

 1990  Gifts in a World of Commodities: The Ideology of the Perfect                       Gift in American Society. Social Analysis 29:19-37.

 

1991  Gifts, Commodities, and Social Relations: A Maussian View of                           Exchange. Sociological Forum 6 (1): 119-136.

 

Daniels, K.R.

1989          Semen Donors: Their Motivations and Attitudes to Their                               Offspring. Journal of Reproductive, Infant Psychology 7: 121-                             127.

 

Fox, Renee and Judith Swazey

 1992 Spare Parts: Organ Replacement in American Society.

          New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

 

Gullestad, Marianne

  1992   The Art of Social Relations. Oslo, Norway: Scandinavian                             Press.

 

Haimes, E.

1993a   Issues of Gender in Gamete donation. Social Science and                                Medicine 36(1):85-93.

 

Haimes, E.

1993b   Do Clinicians Benefit from Gamete Donor Anonymity?

             Human Reproduction 8(9):1518-1520.

 

Handelsman, DJ., Dunn, S.M., Conway, A.J., Boylan, L.M. and Jansen, R.P.S.

1985   Psychological and Attitudinal Profiles in Donors for Artificial                            Insemination. Fertililty and Sterility 43: 95-101.

 

Lessor, R., Reitz, K., Balmaceda, JH. and Asch, R.

1990    A Survey of Public Attitudes Toward Oocyte Donation Between                   Sisters. Human Reproduction 5: 889-892.

 

Levi-Strauss, Claude

  1965   The Principle of Reciprocity in Lewis A. Coser and Bernard                            Rosenberg (eds.) Sociological Theory. New York: Macmillan.

 

Mahlstedt, P.P. and Probasco, K.A.

1991          Sperm Donors: Their Attudites Toward Providing Medical and                              Pyschological Information for Recipient Couples and Donor                              Offspring. Fertility and Sterility 56: 747-753.

 

Malinowski, Bronislaw

  1922   Argonaunts of the Western Pacific. London: Routledge.

 

Mauss, Marcel

  1967   The Gift: Forms and Functions of Exchange in Archaic                                       Societies. New York and London: Norton and Company.

 

Myers, M.F.

 1990   Male Gender-Related Issues in Reproduction and Technology.                                In Stotland, N.L. (ed.) Psychiatric Aspects of Reproductive                              Technology. American Psychiatric Press. Washington, DC pp.                             25-35.

 

Pedersen, P., Neilsen, A., Lauritsen, J.

1994    Psychosocial Aspects of Donor Insemination. Acta Obstertricia             et Gynedological Scandinavica 73:701-705.

 

Purdie, A., Peek, J., Adair, V., Graham, F., Fisher, R.

1994    Attitudes of Parents of Young Children to Sperm Donation--                        Implications for Donor Recruitment. Human Reproduction                             9(7):1355-1358.

 

Ragoné, Heléna

1998    Incontestable Motivations. In Reproducing Reproduction:                             Kinship, Power, and Technological Innovation, Sarah Franklin                            and Heléna Ragoné, eds. Pp.118-131. Philadelphia: University                         of Pennsylvania Press.

 

1996    Chasing the Blood Tie: Surrogates, Adoptive Mothers, and                          Fathers. American Ethnologist 23(2):352-365.

 

1994     Surrogate Motherhood: Conception in the Heart. Boulder and                                  Oxford: Westview Press/HarperCollins.

 

Reame, Nancy

1998   Unintended Consequences: What America Should do About                               Assisted Reproduction. A Health Policy Report to the American                 Academy of Nursing and Institute of Medicine. Washington,                                DC.

 

Rosenberg, H., Epstein, Y.

1995           Follow-up Study of Anonymous Ovum Donors. Human                                      Reproduction 10(10):2741-2747.

 

Sauer, M., Paulson, R.

  1994  Oocyte Donors: A Demographic Analysis of Women at the                       University of Southern California. Human Reproduction 7(5):                               776-728.

 

Sauer, M., Paulson, R.

  1992  Understanding the Current Status of Oocyte Donation in the                           United States: What’s Really Going On Out There? Fertility and             Sterility 58(1):16-18.

 

Schneider, David

  1968   American Kinship: A Cultural Account. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:                         Prentice Hall.

 

Schover, L.R. Rothman, S.A. and Collins, R.I.

1992  The Personality and Motivation of Semen Donors: A                                  Comparison with Oocyte Donors. Human Reproducton 6: 1487-                         1491.

 

Simmel, Georg

  1978   The Philosophy of Money. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

 

Strathern, Marilyn and Sarah Franklin

  1993           Need complete reference.

 

Swartz, Barry

  1967   The Social Psychology of the Gift. The American Journal of                         Sociology 73(1): 1-11.

 

Titmus, Richard

  1971   The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy.                              New York: Pantheon Books.

 

Wolfram, Sybil

  1987   In-Laws and Outlaws: Kinship and Marriage in England.

            Beckenham, England: Croom Helm

 

Zelizer, Viviana

  1985   Pricing the Priceless Child. New York: Basic Books.