|
Nietzsche's Fundamental
Metaphysical Position By Martin
Heidegger
Translated by David Farrell
Krell Nietzsche, Volume Two,
Chapter 26, pp. 198-208 .
| .
-------In the foregoing we
have attempted to portray Nietzsche's fundamental thought - the eternal
return of the same - in its essential import, in its domain, and in the
mode of thinking that is expressly proper to the thought itself, that is,
the mode demanded by the thought as such. In that way we have laid the
foundation for our own efforts to define Nietzsche's fundamental metaphysical position in Western philosophy.
The effort to circumscribe Nietzsche's
fundamental metaphysical position indicates that we are examining his
philosophy in terms of the position assigned it by the history of Western
philosphy hitherto. At the same time, this means that we are expressly
transposing Nietzsche's philosophy to that sole position in which it can
and most unfold the forces of thought that are most proper to it, and this
in the context of inescapable confrontation with prior Western philosophy
as a whole. The fact that in the course of our presentation of the
doctrine of return we have actually come to recognize the region of
thought that must necessarily and preeminently take precedence in every
fruitful reading and appropriating of Nietzschean thought may well be an
important gain; yet when viewed in terms of the essential task, namely the
characterization of Nietzsche's fundamental metaphysical position, such a
gain remains merely provisional.
We shall be able to define
Nietzsche's fundamental metaphysical position in its principal traits if
we ponder the response he gives tot he question concerning the
constitution of being and being's way to be. Now, we know that
Nietzsche offers two answers with regard to being as a whole: being as a
whole is will top power, and being as a whole is eternal occurrence of the
same. yet philosophical interpretations of Nietzsche's philosophy have up
to now been unable to grasp these two simultaneous answers as answers,
indeed as answers that necessarily cohere, because they have not
recognized the questions to which these answers pertain; that is to say,
prior interpretations have not explicitly developed these questions on the
basis of a thoroughgoing articulation of the guiding question. If, on the
contrary, we approach the matter in terms of the developed guiding
question, it becomes apparent that the word "is" in these two major
statements - being as a whole is will to power, and being as a whole is
eternal recurrence of the same - in each case suggests something
different. To say that being as a whole "is" eternal recurrence of the
same means that being as a whole is,
as being, in the manner of eternal
recurrence of the same. The determination "will to power" replies to the
question of being with respect to the
latter's constitution; the determination
"eternal recurrence of the same" replies to the question of being
with its respect to its way to be.
Yet constitution and manner of being do
cohere as determination of the beingness of beings.
Accordingly, in
Nietzsche's philosophy will to power and eternal recurrence of the same
belong together. It is thus right from the start a misunderstanding -
better, an outright mistake - of metaphysical proportions when
commentators try to play off will to power against eternal recurrence of
the same, and especially when they exclude the latter altogether from
metaphysical determinations of being. In truth, the coherence of both must be
grasped. Such coherence is itself essentially defined on the basis of the
coherence of the constitution of beings also
specifies in each case their way to be - indeed, as their proper ground.
What fundamental metaphysical position does Nietzsche's philosophy
assume for itslef on the basis of its response to the guiding question
within Western philosphy, that is to say, within
metaphysics?
Nietzsche's philosphy is the end of metaphysics,
inasmuch as it reverts to the very commencement of Greek thought, taking
up such thought in a way that is peculiar to Nietzsche's philosophy alone.
In this way Nietzsche's philosophy closes the ring that is formed by the
very course of inquiry into being as such as as a whole. yet to what
extent does Nietzsche's thinking revert to the commencement? When we
realize this question we must be clear about one point at the very outset:
Nietzsche by no means recovers the philosphy of the commencement in its
pristine form. Rather, here it is purely a matter of the reemergence of
the essential fundamental positions of the commencement in a transformed
configuration, in such a way for these positions interlock.
What
are the decisive fundamental positions of the commencement? In other
words, what sorts of answers are given to the as yet undeveloped guiding
question, the question as to what being is?
The one answer -roughly
speaking, it is the answer of Parmenides - tells us that being is. An odd sort of
answer, no doubt, yet a very deep one, since that very response determines
for the first time and for all thinkers to come, including Nietzsche, the
meaning of is and Being - permanence and presence, that is, the eternal
present.
The other
answer - roughly speaking, that of
Heraclitus - tells us that being becomes.
The being is in being by virtue of its
permanent becoming, its self-unfolding and eventual dissolution.
To
what extent is Nietzsche's thinking the end? That is to say, how does it
stretch back to both these fundamental determinations of being in such a
way that they come to interlock? Precisely to the extent that Nietzsche
argues that being is as fixated, as permanent; and that it is in perpetual
creation and destruction. Yet being is both
of these, not in an extrinsic way, as one
beside another; rather, being is in its very ground perpetual creation
(Becoming), while as creation it needs what is fixed. Creation needs what
is fixed, first, in order to overcome it, and second, ion order to have
something that has yet to be fixated, something that enables the creative
to advance beyond itself and be transfigured. The essence of being is
Becoming, but what becomes is and has Being only in creative
transfiguration. What is and what becomes are fused in the fundamental
thought that what becomes is inasmuch as in creation
it becomes being and is
becoming. Both such becoming-a-being
becomes a being that comes-to-be, and does so in the perpetual
transformation of what has become firmly fixed and intractable to
something made firm in a liberating transfiguration. *
*
The text is extraordinarily difficult to unravel.Dieses Seiendwerden aber wird
zum werdenden Seienden im standigen Werden des Festgewordenen als eines
Erstarrten zum Festgemachten, als der befreienden
Verklarung. The oxymorons of this highly involuted sentence dramatize
the inevitable petrifaction of Becoming in a metaphysics of Being. Only as
permanence of presence can Becoming come to be. The wording of the
sentence in Heidegger's original manuscript (1937) varies only slightly
from the 1961 Neske text. yet a series of energetic lines draws the word
befreienden, "liberating," into the
sentence, as though to break up all such petrifaction. For the
liberating trasnsfiguration of Becoming is what Heidegger
elsewhere calls the most intrinsic will of Nietzschean
thinking.
Nietzsche once wrote,
at the time when the thought of return first loomed on his horizon, during
the years 1881-82 (XII, 66, number 124): "Let us imprint the emblem of
eternity on our life!" The phrase means: let us introduce an
eternalization to ourselves as beings, and hence to beings as a whole; let
us introduce the transfiguration of what becomes as something that becomes
being; and let us do this in such a way that the eternalization arises
from being itself, originating for being, standing in being.
This
fundamental metaphysical demand - that is, a demand that grapples with the
guiding question of metaphysics - is expressed several years later in a
lengthy not entitled "Recapitulation,"
the title suggesting that the note in just
a few sentences provides a resume of the most important aspects of
Nietzsche's philosphy. (See The Will to
Power, number 617, presumably from early
1886.)* Nietzsche's "Recapitulation" begins with the statement: "To stamp
Becoming with the character of Being - that is the supreme will to power." The sense
is not that one must brush aside and replace Becoming as the impermanent -
for impermanence is what Becoming implies - with being as the permanent.
The sense is that one must shape Becoming as being in such a way that
as becoming, it is preserved, has subsistence, being, is the supreme
will to power. In such recoining the will to power comes to prevail most
purely in its essence.
* As the note on page 19 Volume I of this series relates,
Heidegger employs the "Recapitulation" note (WM, 617) at crucial junctures
throughout his Nietzsche lectures. See, for example NI, 466 and 656; NII,
288 and 339; and p. 228, below. Yet the title "Recapitulation" stems not
from Nietzsche himself but from his assistant and later editor Heinrich
Kuselitz (Peter Gast). Furthermore, the sentences from this long note
which Heidegger neglects to cite by no means corroborate the use he makes
of it. The whole of Nietzsche's sketch (now dated between the end of 1886
and spring of 1887), as it appears in CM, Mp XVII 3b (54), reads as
follows:
To stamp Becoming
with the character of Being - that is the supreme will to power.
Twofold falsification, one by the senses, the other by the mind, in
order to preserve a world of being, of perdurance, of equivalence, etc.
That everything recurs is the closes approximation of a world of
Becoming to one of Being: peak of the meditation. The condemnation of
and dissatisfaction with whatever becomes derives from values that are
attributable to being: after such a world of Being had first been
invented. The metamorphoses of being (body, God, ideas, laws of
nature, formulas, etc.) "Being" as semblance; inversion of values:
semblance was that which conferred value - Knowledge itself
impossible within Becoming, how then is knowledge possible? As error
concerning itself, as will to power, as will to deception. Becoming
as invention volition self-denial, the overcoming of oneself not a
subject but a doing, establishing creative, not "causes and
effects." Art as the will to overcome Becoming, as "eternalization,"
but shortsighted, depending on perspective repeating a small scale, as
it were, the tendency of the whole. What all life exhibits, to be
observed as a reduced formula for the universal tendency: hence a new
grip on the concept "life" as will to power. Instead of "cause and
effect," the mutual struggle of things that become, often with the
absorption of the opponent; the number of things in becoming not
constant. Inefficacy of the old ideals for interpreting the whole of
occurrence, once one has recognized their animal origins and utility;
all of them, furthermore, contradicting life. Inefficacy of the
mechanistic theory - gives the impression of meaninglessness. The
entire idealism of humanity hitherto is about to turn into nihilism -
into belief in absolute worthlessness, that is to say, senselessness . .
. Annihilation of ideals, the new desert, the new arts, by means of
which we can endure it, we amphibians. Presupposition: bravery,
patience, no "turning back" not hurrying forward. N.B., Zarathustra,
always parodying prior values, on the basis of his won
abundance.
What is this recoining, in which whatever
becomes comes to be being? It is the reconfiguration of what becomes in
terms of its supreme possibilities, a reconfiguration in which what
becomes is transfigured and attains subsistence in its very dimensions and
domains. This recoining is a creating. To create, in the sense of creation
out beyond oneself, is most intrinsically this: to stand in the moment of
decision, in which what has prevailed hitherto, our endowment, is directed
toward a projected task. When it is so directed, the endowment is
preserved. The "momentary" character of creation is the essence of actual,
actuating eternity, which achieves its greatest breadth and keenest edge
as the moment of eternity in the return of the same. The recoining of what
becomes into being - will to power in its supreme configuration - is in
its most profound essence something that occurs in the "glance of an eye"
as eternal recurrence of the same. the will to power, as constitution of
being, is as it is solely on the basis of the \way to be which Nietzsche
projects for being as a whole: Will to
power, in its essence and according to its inner possibility is eternal
recurrence of the same.
The aptness
of our interpretation is demonstrated unequivocally in that very fragment
which bears the title "Recapitulation." After the statement we have
already cited - "To stamp Becoming with the character of Being - that is
the supreme will to power" - we soon read the following sentence: "That everything reverts is the closes approximation of a
world of Becoming to one of Being: peak of the
meditation." It would scarcely be possible
to say in a more lucid fashion, first, how and on what basis the stamping
of Being on Becoming is meant to be even and precisely during the period
when the thought of will to power appears to attain preeminence, remains
the thought which Nietzsche's philosphy things without cease.
(During our discussion of the plans for
Nietzsche's magnum opus (see page 160, above), several students noted that
whereas sketches for such plans from the final year of Nietzsche's
creative life (1888) mention Dionysos in the titles of their projected
fourth and final books, our lecture course up to now has said nothing
about this god.
Nevertheless, we ought to pay close attention to
the phrases that follow the god's name in these titles: "philosophy of
eternal return," or simply "philosophos."
Such phrases suggest
that what the words Dionysos and
Dionysian
mean to Nietzsche will be heard and understood only if the "eternal
return of the same" is thought. In turn, that which eternally recurs as
the same and in such wise is, that is, perpetually presences, has the
ontological constitution of "will to power." The mythic name
Dionysos
will become an epithet that has been thought through in the
sense intended by Nietzsche the thinker only when we try to think the
coherence
of "will to power" and "eternal return of the same"; and that means only
when we seek those determinations of Being which from the outset of
Greek thought guide all thinking about being as such and as a whole.
(Two texts which appeared several years ago treat the matters of
Dionysos and the Dionysian:
Walter F. Otto, Dionysos: Myth and Cult, 1933; and Karl Reinhardt, "Nietzsche's 'Plaint of
Ariadne,'" in the journal Die Antike,
1935, published separately in
1936.)*
* The paragraphs contained within parentheses appear as an
indented extract in the Neske edition as they do here. Heidegger's
original manuscript from the summer of 1937 does not show these
paragraphs. Surprisingly, there is no extant, Abschrift
or
typescript of this course; nor is the typescript that went to the
printer in 1961 available for inspection. As a result, the date of the
passage remains uncertain. My own surmise is that Heigegger added the
note not long after the semester drew to a close, the reference to
students questions and to those tow works on Dionysos that had
"recently" been published make it highly unlikely that the note was
added as late as 1960-61. The works Heidegger refers us to are of course
still available - and are still very much wroth reading. Walter F. Otto,
Dionysos: Mythos and Kultus (Frankfurt am Main: V. Klostermann, 1933):
Reinhardt's "Nietzsche's Klage der Ariadne" appears now in Karl
Reinhardt, Vermachtrus der Antike Gesammelte Essays zur Philosophie und
Geschichtsschreiburg, edited by Carl Becker (Gottingen: Vandernhock
& Ruprecht, 1960), pp. 310-33. See note 20 of the Analysis, p. 275,
for further discussion of the Reinhardt article.
Nietzche conjoins in one both of the fundamental
determinations of being that emerge from the commencement of Western
philosophy to wit, being as becoming and being as permanence. that "one"
is his most essential thought - the eternal recurrence of the
same.
Yet can we designate Nietzsche's way of grappling with the
commencement of Western philosophy as an end? Is it not rather a
reawakening of the commencement? Is it not therefore itself a commencement
and hence the very opposite of an end? It is nonetheless the case that
Nietzsche's fundamental metaphysical position is the end of Western
philosophy. For what is decisive is not that the fundamental
determinations of the commencement are conjoined and that Nietzsche's thinking
stretches back to the commencement; what is metaphysically essential it
the way in which these things transpire. The question is whether Nietzsche
reverts to the incipient commencement, to the commencement as a
commencing. And here our answer must be: no he does not.
Neither
Nietzsche nor any thinker prior to him - even and especially not that one
who before Nietzsche first thought the history of philosophy in a
philosophical way, namely, Hegel - revert to the incipient commencement.
Rather, they invariably apprehend the commencement in the sole light of a
philosophy in decline form it, a philosophy that arrests the commencement
- to wit, the philosophy of Plato. Here we cannot demonstrate this matter
in any detail Nietzsche himself quite early characterizes his philosphy as
inverted Platonism; yet the inversion does not eliminate the fundamentally
Platonic position. Rather, precisely because it seems to eliminate the
Platonic position, Nietzsche's inversion represents the entrenchment of
that position.
What remains essential, however, is the following:
when Nietzsche's metaphysical thinking reverts to the commencement, the
circle closes. yet inasmuch as it is the already terminated commencement
and not the incipient one that prevails there, the circle itself grows
inflexible, loses whatever of the commencement it once had. When the
circle closes in this way it no longer releases any possibilities for essential
inquiry into the guiding question. Metaphysics - treatment of the guiding
question - is at an end. That seems a bootless, comfortless insight, a
conclusion which like a dying tone signals ultimate cessation. Yet such is
not the case.
Because Nietzsche's fundamental metaphysical position
is the end of metaphysics in the designated sense, it performs the
grandest and most profound gathering - that is, accomplishment - of all
the essential fundamental positions in Western philosophy since Plato and
in the light of Platonism. It does so form within a fundamental position
remains an actual, actuating fundamental metaphysical position only if it
in turn is developed in all its essential forces and regions of dominion
in the direction of its counterpositon.
For thinking that looks beyond it.
Nietzsche's philosophy, which is inherently a turning against what lies
behind it, must itslef come to be a forward-looking counterposition. Yet
since Nietzsche's fundamental position in Western metaphysics constitutes
the end of that metaphysics, it can be the counterposition. for our other
commencement only if the later adopts a questioning stance
vis-a-vis the initial commencement - as one which in its proper
originality is only now commencing. After everything we have said, the
questioning intended here can only be the unfolding of a more original
inquiry. Such questioning must be the unfolding of the prior,
all-determining, and commanding question of philosphy, t he guiding
question, "What is being?" out of
itself and out beyond itself.
Nietzsche himself once chose a phrase to
designate what we are calling his fundamental metaphysical position, a
phrase that is often cited and is readily taken as a way to characterize
his philosphy armor fati, love of necessity. (See the Epilogue to Nietzsche contra Wagner; VIII, 206).* Yet the phrase expresses Nietzsche's
fundamental metaphysical position only when we understand the two words
armor and fatum - and, above all, their conjunction - in terms of
Nietzsche's ownmost thinking, only when we avoid mixing our fortuitous
and familiar notions into it.
* The text Heidegger refers us
to begins as follows:
I have often asked myself if I am not more
profoundly indebted to the most difficult years of my life than to any of
the others. What my innermost nature instructs me is that all necessity -
viewed from the heights, in terms of an economy on a grand scale - is also
what is inherently useful: one should not merely put up with it, one
should love it. . . Armor fati: that is my innermost
nature.
Nietzsche repeats the formula twice in
Ecce
Homo (II, 10, and III, "Der Fall Wagner," 4); the first time as
the ultimate explanation of his "discernment":
"My formula for
greatness in a human being is armor fati - love of necessity: that one
does not will to have anything different, neither forward nor backward nor
into all eternity. Not merely to bear necessity, though must less to cloak
it - all Idealism is mendacity in the face of necessity - but to love."
Nietzsche, Ecce Homo (II, 10 and III, "Der Fall Wagner,"
4)
Nietzsche had first cited the formula six years earlier, at the
outset of Book IV of The Gay Science, as the very essence of
affirmation:
"I want to learn better how to see the necessity in
things as what is beautiful - in that way I shall become one of those who
make things beautiful. Armor fati: let this be my love from now
on!"
And he had written to Franz Overbeck, also in 1882, that he
was possessed of "a fatalistic trust in God" which he preferred to call
armor fati; and he boasted, "I would stick my head down a lion's throat,
not to mention . . . "
The fullest statement concerning amor fati,
however appears as WM, 104) (CM, W II 7a (32), from spring-summer, 1888)
Although the note as a whole merits reprinting, and rereading, the
following extract contains the essential lines. Nietzsche explains that
his "experimental philosophy" aims to advance beyond nihilism to the very
opposite of nihilism.
"to a Dionysian yes-saying to the world as it
is, without reduction, exception, or selection; it wants eternal
circulation - the same things, the same logic and dialogic of implication.
Supreme state to which a philosopher may attain; taking a stand in
Dionysian fashion on behalf of existence. My formula for this is
armor
fati.
Amor - love - is to be understood as will, the will that wants
what ever it loves to be what it is in its essence. The supreme will of
this kind, the most expansive and decisive will, is the will as
transfiguration. Such a will erects and exposes what it wills in its
essence to the supreme possibilities of its Being.
Fatum - necessity - is to
be understood, not as a fatality that is inscrutable, implacable, and
overwhelming, but as that turning of need which unveils itslef in the
awestruck moment as an eternity, an eternity pregnant with the Becoming of
being as a whole: circulus vitiosus
deus.
Armor fati is the
transfiguring will to belong to what is most in being among beings. A
fatum is
unpropitious, disruptive, and devastating to the one who merely stands
there and lets it whelm him. That fatum is sublime and is
supreme desire, however, to one who appreciates and grasps the fact that
he belongs to his fate insofar as he is a creator, that is, one who is
ever resolute. His knowing this is nothing else than the knowledge which
of necessity resonates in his love.
The thinker inquires into being
as a whole and as such; into the world as such. Thus with his very first
step he always thinks out beyond the world, and so at the same time back
to it. he thinks in the direction of that sphere within which a world
becomes world. Whenever that sphere is not incessantly called by name,
called aloud, wherever it is held silently in the most interior
questioning, it is thought most purely and profoundly. For what is held in
silence is genuinely preserved, as preserved it is most intimate and
actual. What to common sense looks like "atheism," and has to look like
ti, is at bottom the very opposite. In the same, wherever the matters of
death and the nothing are treated. Being and Being alone is thought most
deeply - whereas those who ostensibly occupy themselves solely with
"reality" flounder in nothingness.
Supremely thoughtful utterance
does not consist simply in growing taciturn when it is a matter of saying
what is properly to be said; it consists in saying the mater in such a way
that it is named in nonsaying. The utterance of thinking is a telling
silence.* Such utterance corresponds to the most profound essence of
language, which has its origin in silence. As one in touch with telling
silence, the thinker, in a way peculiar to him, rises to the rank of a
poet, yet he remains eternally distinct form the poet, just as the poet in
turn remains eternally distinct from the thinker.
Everything in the
hero's sphere turns to tragedy; everything in the demigod's sphere turns
to satyr-play; and everything in God's sphere turns to . . . to what?
"world" perhaps?
*
Erschweigen, an active or telling
silence, is what Heidegger elsewhere discusses under the rubric of
sigetics (from the Greed
sigao, to keep silent). For him it
is the power "logic" of a thinking that inquires into the other
commencement. |