IV The Nature and
Significance of Goethe's Writings on Organic
Development
The
great significance of Goethe's morphological works is to be
sought in the fact that in them the theoretical basis and
method for studying organic entities are established, and this
is a scientific deed of the first order.
If
one is to do justice to this rightly, one must above all bear
in mind the great difference existing between the phenomena of
inorganic nature and those of organic nature. A phenomenon of
the first kind, for example, is the impact of two elastic
balls upon one another. If one ball is at rest and the other
ball strikes it from a certain direction and with a certain
velocity, then the first ball is likewise given a certain
direction and velocity. If it is a matter then of
comprehending such a phenomenon, this can be achieved
only by our transforming into concepts what is directly there
for the senses. We would succeed in this to the extent that
nothing of a sense-perceptibly real nature remained that we
had not permeated conceptually. We see one ball approach and
strike the other, which then goes on moving. We have
comprehended this phenomenon when, from the mass,
direction, and velocity of the first ball, and from the mass
of the second, we can determine the direction and velocity of
the second ball; when we see that under the given conditions
this phenomenon must necessarily occur. But this means
nothing other than: that which offers itself to our senses
must appear as a necessary consequence of what we have
to postulate ideally beforehand. If this is the case, then we
can say that concept and phenomenon coincide. There is
nothing in the concept that is not also in the phenomenon, and
nothing in the phenomenon that is not also in the concept.
Now we must take a closer look into those relationships out of
which a phenomenon of inorganic nature occurs as a necessary
consequence. The important fact arises here that the
sense-perceptible processes of inorganic nature are determined
by factors that likewise belong to the sense world. In our
example, mass, velocity, and direction — i.e., exclusively
factors belonging to the sense world — come into
consideration. Nothing further arises as a determining factor
for the phenomenon. It is only the directly sense-perceptible
factors that determine one another. A conceptual grasp
of such processes is therefore nothing other than a tracing of
something sense-perceptibly real back to something
sense-perceptibly real. Spatial-temporal relationships, mass,
weight, or sense-perceptible forces such as light or warmth
call forth phenomena that themselves belong in the same
category. A body is heated and increases thereby in volume;
the heating and the expanding both belong to the sense world;
both the cause and the effect do so. We therefore do not need
to go outside the sense world at all in order to comprehend
such processes. We merely trace, within the sense
world, one phenomenon back to another. When we therefore
explain such a phenomenon, i.e., want to permeate it
conceptually, we do not need to take up into the concept any
elements other than those which are observably
perceptible to our senses. We can observe everything that we
want to comprehend. And the congruence of perception
(phenomenon) and concept consists in this. Nothing in the
processes remains obscure to us, because we know the
relationships from which they follow. With this, we have
elaborated upon the character of inorganic nature and have
shown at the same time to what extent we can explain inorganic
nature out of itself, without going out of or beyond
it. Now one has never doubted this explainability, ever since
one first began to think about the nature of these things. One
has not, to be sure, always gone through the above train of
thought from which the possibility of a congruence of concept
and perception follows; but still one has never hesitated to
explain phenomena out of the nature of their own being in the
way indicated. [ 31 ]
But
matters were different, up until Goethe, with respect
to the phenomena of the organic world. In the case of
an organism, sense-perceptible factors appear — form, size,
colour, warmth conditions of an organ, for example — that are
not determined by factors of the same kind. One cannot say of
the plant, for example, that the size, form, location, etc.,
of the roots determine the sense-perceptible factors of the
leaf or blossom. A body for which this were the case would not
be an organism but rather a machine. It must be admitted that
all the sense-perceptible factors of a living being do not
manifest as a result of other sense-perceptible factors, [ 32 ] as is the case with
inorganic nature. On the contrary, in an organism, all
sense-perceptible qualities manifest as the result of a factor
that is no longer sense-perceptible. They manifest as
the result of a higher unity hovering over the
sense-perceptible processes. It is not the shape of the root
which determines that of the trunk, nor the trunk's shape
which determines that of the leaf, and so on, rather, all
these forms are determined by something standing over them
that itself is not again a form observable by the senses;
these forms do exist for one another, but not as a result of
one another. They do not mutually determine one another, but
rather are all determined by something else. Here we cannot
trace what we perceive with our senses back to other
sense-perceptible factors; we must take up, into the concept
of the processes, elements that do not belong to the world of
the senses; we must go out of and beyond the sense
world. Observation no longer suffices; we must
grasp the unity conceptually if we want to explain the
phenomena. Because of this, however, a separation occurs
between observation and concept; they no longer seem to
coincide with each other; the concept hovers over what is
observed. It becomes difficult to see the connection. Whereas
in inorganic nature concept and reality were one, here they
seem to diverge and actually to belong to two different
worlds. The observation that offers itself directly to the
senses no longer seems to bear within itself its own basis,
its own being. The object does not seem explainable out of
itself, but rather from something else. Because the object
appears in a way not governed by the laws of the sense world,
but is there for the senses nevertheless, appears to the
senses, it is then as though we stood here before an insoluble
contradiction in nature, as though a chasm existed between
inorganic phenomena, which are comprehensible through
themselves, and organic beings, in which an intrusion into the
laws of nature occurs, in which universally valid laws seem
suddenly to be broken. Up until Goethe, in fact,
science generally considered this chasm to exist; he was the
first to succeed in speaking the word that solved the riddle.
Before him, one thought that only inorganic nature was
explainable out of itself; man's ability to know ceases when
confronted by organic nature. One can best estimate the
greatness of the deed Goethe accomplished when one considers
that the great reformer of philosophy in recent time, Kant,
not only shared completely in that old error, but even sought,
in fact, to find a scientific foundation for the view that the
human spirit will never succeed in explaining organic
entities. He saw the possibility, to be sure, of an intellect
— of an intellectus archetypus, of an intuitive
intellect — to which it would be granted to see into the
relationship of concept and reality in organic beings just as
it does in inorganic things; only, he denied to man himself
the possibility of any such intellect (Verstand). [ 33 ] For Kant, it is
supposedly characteristic of the human intellect that it can
think of the unity, the concept of a thing, only as resulting
from the interaction of its parts — as an analytical
generalization gained by a process of abstraction — but not in
such a way that each individual part manifests as the outflow
of a definite concrete (synthetical) unity, of a concept in an
intuitive form. For this reason, it is also supposedly
impossible for the intellect to explain organic nature,
because organic nature would have to be thought of, indeed, as
working from the whole into the parts. Kant says about this:
“It is characteristic of our intellect, therefore, with
respect to our power of judgment, that it does not determine
knowledge through itself, does not determine what is
particular through what is general, and that therefore the
particular cannot be traced back to the general.” [ 34 ] According to this,
we would therefore have to renounce all knowledge, with regard
to organic entities, of the necessary connection between the
idea of the whole — which can only be thought — and what
manifests to our senses in space and time. According to Kant,
we must limit ourselves to the recognition that such a
connection exists; but the logical challenge to know how the
general thought, the idea, steps out of itself and manifests
itself as sense-perceptible reality, this supposedly cannot be
fulfilled with respect to organisms. Rather we would have to
assume that concept and reality confront each other here
without mediation; and that some influence lying outside them
both creates them in somewhat the same way a person, according
to an idea he has thought up, constructs some composite thing
or other — a machine, for example. In this way the possibility
of an explanation of the world of organisms was denied, its
impossibility in fact seemingly proven.
This is how matters stood when Goethe undertook
to devote himself to the organic sciences. But he entered into
these studies after preparing himself for them in a most
appropriate way, through repeated readings of the philosopher
Spinoza.
Goethe took up Spinoza for the first time in the
spring of 1774. In Poetry and Truth, he says of this,
his first acquaintance with the philosopher: “That is, after
vainly looking around in the whole world for a means of
educating my strange being, I finally happened upon the
Ethics of this man.” In the summer of the same year,
Goethe met with Friedrich Jacobi. The latter, who had come
more thoroughly to terms with Spinoza — as his letters of 1785
about Spinoza's teachings show — was entirely qualified to
lead Goethe more deeply into the essential nature of the
philosopher. Spinoza was also very much discussed at that
time, for in Goethe “everything was still in its first effects
and counter-effects, fermenting and seething.” Somewhat later,
he found a book in his father's library whose author heatedly
opposed Spinoza, even distorting him, in fact, into a total
caricature. This gave Goethe the stimulus to occupy himself
seriously once more with the profound thinker. In Spinoza's
writings he found elucidation on the deepest scientific
questions that he was then capable of raising. In 1784, the
poet reads Spinoza with Frau von Stein. On November 19, 1784,
he writes to her: “I am bringing Spinoza along in Latin, in
which everything is much clearer ...” The effect of this
philosopher upon Goethe was now immense. Goethe himself was
always clear about this. In 1816, he writes to Zelter: “Except
for Shakespeare and Spinoza, I do not know that any departed
soul has had such an effect upon me (as Linnaeus).” He regards
Shakespeare and Spinoza therefore as the two spirits who have
exerted the greatest influence on him. The manner in which
this influence now manifested itself with respect to his
studies of organic development becomes clearest to us if we
consider a statement about Lavater from Goethe's Italian
Journey; Lavater was also in fact a proponent of the view
generally prevalent then that something living can arise only
through an influence that does not lie in the nature of the
entity itself, through a violation of the general laws of
nature. Goethe then wrote the following words about this:
“Recently I found, in a pitiful, apostolically monkish
declamation of the Zürich prophet, the nonsensical words that
everything that has life lives by something outside
itself. Or it sounded something like that. Now a
missionary can write down something like that, and when he is
revising it no good spirit tugs at his sleeve.” Now that is
expressed entirely in the spirit of Spinoza. Spinoza makes a
distinction between three kinds of knowledge. The first kind
is that in which upon hearing or reading certain words we
recall certain things and form certain mental pictures of
these things which are similar to the pictures by which we
represent the things to ourselves pictorially. The second kind
of knowledge is that in which, out of sufficient mental
pictures of the characteristics of things, we form general
concepts for ourselves. The third kind of knowledge, however,
is that in which we advance from an adequate picture of the
real being of certain attributes of God to an adequate
knowledge of the being of things. Spinoza calls this kind of
knowledge scientia intuitiva, knowledge in
beholding. This last, the highest kind of knowledge, is
that for which Goethe strove. One must above all be clear
about what Spinoza meant by this The things are to be known in
such a way that we recognize within their being certain
attributes of God. Spinoza's God is the idea-content of the
world, the driving principle that supports and carries
everything. Now one can picture this either in such a way that
one takes this principle to be an independent being — existing
by itself, separated off from finite beings — that has these
finite things outside itself, governs them, and causes them to
interact. Or, on the other hand, one can picture this being as
having merged into finite things in such a way that it is no
longer over and outside them, but rather now exists only
within them. This view in no way denies that primal
principle; it acknowledges it entirely; only, it regards this
principle as having been poured out into the world. The
first view regards the finite world as a manifestation of the
infinite, but this infinite remains with its own being intact;
it relinquishes nothing of itself. It does not go out of
itself; it remains what it was before it manifested itself.
The second view also regards the finite world as a
manifestation of the infinite, only it assumes that this
infinite, in becoming manifest, has gone entirely out of
itself, has laid itself, its own being and life, into its
creation in such a way that it now exists only within this
creation. Now since our activity of knowing is obviously a
becoming aware of the essential being of things, and since
this being can after all consist only in the involvement a
finite being has in the primal principle of all things, our
activity of knowing must then mean a becoming aware of that
infinite within the things. [ 35 ] Now, as we have
described above, it was readily assumed, before Goethe, with
respect to inorganic nature, that one could explain it out of
itself, that it carries within itself its own substantiation
and essential being, but that this is not the case with
organic nature. Here one could not know, within an object
itself, that essential being that manifests itself within the
object. One therefore assumed this being to be outside the
object. In short: one explained organic nature according to
the first view and inorganic nature according to the second.
As we have seen, Spinoza had proven the necessity for a
unified knowledge. He was too much the philosopher to have
been able also to extend this theoretical requirement out over
the specialized area of organic science. It remained for
Goethe to do this now. Not only his statement about Spinoza
quoted above, but also numerous others show us that Goethe
adhered decisively to Spinoza's views. In Poetry and
Truth: “Nature works according to laws that are eternal,
necessary, and so divine that even the Divinity Himself could
change nothing about them.” And, in connection with Jacobi's
book, Of Divine Things and their Manifestation, [ 36 ] Goethe remarks:
“How could the book of such a beloved friend be welcome to me
when I had to see developed in it the thesis that nature
conceals God. With my pure, deep, inborn, and trained way of
looking at things, which had taught me absolutely to see
God in nature, nature in God, such that this way of
picturing things constituted the foundation of my whole
existence, would not such a peculiar, one-sidedly limited
statement estrange me forever in spirit from this most noble
man whose heart I revered and loved?” Goethe was completely
conscious of the great step he was taking in science; he
recognized that by breaking down the barriers between
inorganic and organic nature and by consistently carrying
through on Spinoza's way of thinking, he was giving science a
significant turn. We find his knowledge of this fact expressed
in his essay Power to Judge in Beholding
(Anschauende Urteilskraft). After he had found, in the
Critique of Judgment, the Kantian establishment of the
in ability of the human intellect to explain an organism, as
we described above, Goethe expresses his opposition to it in
this way: “To be sure, the author (Kant) seems here to point
to a divine intellect; but when we, in fact, lift ourselves in
the moral sphere into a higher region through belief in God,
virtue, and immortality and mean to draw near to the primal
being, so likewise, in the intellectual realm, it could very
well be the case that we would make ourselves worthy, through
beholding an ever-creating nature, of participating
spiritually in its productions. Since I had, after all,
ceaselessly pressed on, at first unconsciously and out of an
inner urge, toward that primal archetypal element, since I had
even succeeded in building up a presentation of this which was
in accordance with nature, nothing more could keep me then
from courageously under taking the adventure of reason,
as the old man of Königsberg himself calls it.”
The
essential thing about a process of inorganic nature — a
process belonging merely to the sense world, in other words —
consists in the fact that it is caused and determined by
another process which likewise belongs only to the sense
world. Let us assume now that the causal process consists of
the elements m, d, and v (mass, direction, and velocity of a
moving elastic ball) and that the resulting process consists
of the elements m', d', and v'; then what m, d, and v are will
always determine what m', d', and v' are. If I now want to
comprehend the process, I must represent the whole process,
consisting of cause and effect, in one common concept. But
this concept is not of such a sort that it could lie within
the process itself and determine the process. The concept now
brings both processes together into one common expression: It
does not cause and determine. Only the objects of the sense
world determine each other. The elements m, d, and v are
elements that are also perceptible to the external senses. The
concept appears there only in order to serve man's spirit as a
means of drawing things together; it expresses something that
is not ideally, conceptually real, but rather is
sense-perceptibly real. And that something which it expresses
is a sense-perceptible object. Knowledge of inorganic nature
is based upon the possibility of grasping the outer world
through the senses and of expressing its interactions through
concepts. Kant saw the possibility of knowing things in this
way as the only way man has. He called this thinking
“discursive.” What we want to know is an
external perception; the concept, the unity that draws things
together, is merely a means. But if we wanted to know organic
nature, we would then have to consider the ideal element, the
conceptual factor, not as something that expresses or
signifies something else, but rather we would have to know the
ideal element as such; it would have to have a content
of its own, stemming from itself, and not from the
spatial-temporal world of the senses. That unity which, in
inorganic nature, man's spirit merely abstracts from the
world, would have to build upon itself, would have to develop
itself out of its own self, would have to be fashioned
in accordance with its own being and not according to the
influences of other objects. Man is supposedly denied the
ability to apprehend such an entity as this that develops
itself out of itself and that manifests itself out of its own
power. Now what is necessary for such an apprehension? A power
of judgment that can impart to a thought yet another substance
(Stoff) than one merely taken up by the outer senses, a
power of judgment that can apprehend not merely what is
sense-perceptible, but also what is purely ideal, by itself,
separated from the sense world. Now one can call a concept
that is not taken from the sense world by abstraction, but
rather has a content flowing out of itself and only out of
itself, an “intuitive concept” and knowledge of this
concept an “intuitive” one. What follows from this is clear:
An organism can be apprehended only in an intuitive
concept. Goethe shows, through what he does, that it is
granted to the human being to know in this way.
What prevails in the inorganic world is the
interaction of the parts of a series of phenomena; it is their
reciprocal determining of each other. This is not the case in
the organic world. There, one part of an entity does not
determine the other, but rather the whole (the idea), out of
itself and in accordance with its own being, determines each
individual part. One can follow Goethe in calling this
self-determining whole an “entelechy.” An entelechy is
therefore a power that, out of itself, calls itself into
existence. What comes into manifestation also has a
sense-perceptible existence, but this is determined by that
entelechical principle. From this also arises the seeming
contradiction. An organism determines itself out of itself,
fashions its characteristics in accordance with a presupposed
principle, and yet it is sense-perceptibly real. It has
therefore arrived at its sense-perceptible reality in a
completely different way than the other objects of the sense
world; thus it seems to have arisen in an unnatural way. But
it is also entirely explainable that an organism, in its
externality, is just as susceptible to the influences of the
sense world as is any other body. The stone falling from a
roof can strike a living entity just as well as an inorganic
object. An organism is connected with the outer world through
its intake of nourishment, etc.; all the physical
circumstances of the outer world affect it. Of course this can
also occur only insofar as the organism is an object of the
sense world, a spatial-temporal object. This object of the
outer world then, this entelechical principle that has come
into existence, is the outer manifestation of the organism.
But since the organism is subject not only to its own laws of
development but also to the conditions of the outer world,
since it is not only what it should be in accordance with the
being of the self-determining entelechical principle, but also
is what other dependencies and influences have made it,
therefore the organism never seems, as it were, to accord
fully with itself, never seems obedient merely to its own
being. Here human reason enters and forms for itself, in
idea, an organism that is not in accordance with the
influences of the outer world, but rather corresponds only to
that entelechical principle. Every coincidental influence that
has nothing to do with the organism as such falls away
entirely here. This idea, now, that corresponds purely to what
is organic in the organism is the idea of the archetypal
organism; it is Goethe's typus. From this one can also
see the great justification for this idea of the typus.
This idea is not merely an intellectual concept; it is
what is truly organic in every organism, without which an
organism would not be one. This idea is, in fact, more real
than any individual real organism, because it manifests itself
in every organism. It also expresses the essential
nature of an organism more fully, more purely
than any individual, particular organism. It is
acquired in an essentially different way than the concept of
an inorganic process. This latter is drawn from, abstracted
from, reality; it is not at work within reality; the idea of
the organism, however, is active, is at work as entelechy
within the organism; it is, in the form grasped by our reason,
only the being of the entelechy itself. This idea does not
draw the experience together; it brings about what is
to be experienced. Goethe expresses this in the following
words: “Concept is summation, idea is result of
experience; to find the sum requires intellect; to grasp the
result requires reason” (Aphorisms in Prose). This
explains that kind of reality which belongs to the Goethean
archetypal organism (archetypal plant or archetypal animal).
This Goethean method is clearly the only possible one by which
to penetrate into the essential nature of the world of
organisms.
With respect to the inorganic, the fact should
be regarded as essential that the phenomenon, in all its
manifoldness, is not identical with the lawfulness that
explains it, but rather points, merely, to this lawfulness as
to something external to it. The observation (the material
element of knowledge, given us by the outer senses) and the
concept (the formal element, by which we recognize the
observation as necessitated) confront each other as two
elements that objectively require each other, it is true; but
they do so in such a way that the concept does not lie within
the individual parts of a series of phenomena themselves but
rather within a relationship of these parts to each other.
This relationship, which brings the manifoldness into a
unified whole, is founded within the individual parts
of the given, but as a whole (as a unity) it does not
come to real, concrete manifestation. Only the parts of
this relationship come to outer existence — in the object. The
unity, the concept, first comes to manifestation as
such within our intellect. The intellect has the task of
drawing together the manifoldness of the phenomenon; it
relates itself to the manifoldness as its sum. We have
to do here with a duality: with the manifold thing that we
observe, and with the unity that we think. In
organic nature the parts of the manifoldness of an entity do
not stand in such an external relationship to each other. The
unity comes into reality in the observed entity simultaneously
with the manifoldness, as something identical with the
manifoldness. The relationship of the individual parts of a
phenomenal whole (an organism) has become a real one. It no
longer comes to concrete manifestation merely within our
intellect, but rather within the object itself, and in the
object it brings forth the manifoldness out of itself. The
concept does not have the role merely of summation, of being a
combiner that has its object outside itself; the
concept has become completely one with the object. What
we observe is no longer different from that by which we think
the observed; we are observing the concept as the idea itself.
Therefore, Goethe calls the ability by which we comprehend
organic nature the power to judge in beholding
(Anschauende Urteilskraft). What explains (the formal
element of knowledge, the concept) and what is explained (the
material, the beheld) are identical. The idea by which we
grasp the organic is therefore essentially different from the
concept by which we explain the inorganic; the idea does not
merely draw together — like a sum — a given manifoldness, but
rather sets forth its own content out of itself. The idea is
the result of the given (of experience), is concrete
manifestation. Herein lies the reason why in inorganic natural
science we speak of laws (natural laws) and explain the facts
by them, and in organic nature, on the other hand, we do this
by types. The law is not one and the same with
the manifoldness of the observed that the law governs; the law
stands over it; in the typus, however, the ideal
element and the real element have become a unity; the
manifoldness can be explained only as going forth from a point
of the whole, the whole that is identical with the
manifoldness.
In
Goethe's knowledge of this relationship between the science of
the inorganic and that of the organic lies what is so
significant in his research. One is in error, therefore, when
today one often explains his research as a forerunner of that
monism which wants to found a unified view of nature —
comprising both the organic and the inorganic — by endeavoring
to trace what is organic back to the same laws
(mechanical-physical categories and laws of nature) by which
the inorganic is determined. We have seen how Goethe conceives
a monistic view to be. The way he explains the organic is
essentially different from the way he proceeds with respect to
the inorganic. He wants to be sure that the mechanistic way of
explaining things is strictly avoided with respect to what is
of a higher nature (see his Aphorisms in Prose). He
criticizes Kieser and Link for wanting to trace organic
phenomena back to inorganic activity.
What gave rise to the erroneous view about
Goethe indicated above was the relationship into which he
brought himself to Kant with respect to the possibility of a
knowledge of organic nature. But when Kant asserts that our
intellect is not able to explain organic nature, he certainly
does not mean by this that organic nature rests upon
mechanical lawfulness and that he is only unable to grasp it
as resulting from mechanical-physical categories. For Kant,
the reason for this inability lies, rather, precisely in the
fact that our intellect can explain only mechanical-physical
things and that the being of the organism is not of this
nature. Were it so, then the intellect, by virtue of the
categories at its command, could very well grasp its being. It
is definitely not Goethe's thought now to explain the organic
world as a mechanism in spite of Kant; but rather he
maintains that we by no means lack the ability to know that
higher kind of nature's working which establishes the
essential being of the organic.
As
we consider what has just been said, we are confronted right
away by an essential difference between inorganic and organic
nature. Since in inorganic nature any process whatever can
cause another, and this in turn yet another, and so on, the
sequence of occurrences seems nowhere to be a closed one.
Everything is in continuous interaction, without any one
particular group of objects being able to close itself off
from the effects of others. The sequences of inorganic
activity have nowhere a beginning nor an end; there is only a
chance connection between one happening and the next. If a
stone falls to earth, the effect it produces depends upon the
chance form of the object on which it falls. It is a different
matter now with an organism. Here the unity is primary. The
entelechy, built upon itself, comprises a number of
sense-perceptible developmental forms of which one must be the
first and another the last; in which one form can always only
follow the other in an altogether definite way. The ideal
unity puts forth out of itself a series of sense-perceptible
organs in a certain sequence in time and in a particular
spatial relationship, and closes itself off in an altogether
definite way from the rest of nature. It puts forth its
various states out of itself. These can therefore also be
grasped only when one studies the development of successive
states as they emerge from an ideal unity; i.e., an organic
entity can be understood only in its becoming, in its
developing. An inorganic body is closed off, rigid, can only
be moved from outside, is inwardly immobile. An organism is
restlessness within itself, ever transforming it self from
within, changing, producing metamorphoses. The following
statements of Goethe refer to this: “Reason is oriented toward
what is becoming, the intellect toward what has become; the
former does not bother itself about purpose (wozu?);
the latter does not ask about origin (woher?). Reason
rejoices in development; intellect wishes to hold everything
fixed in order to use it” (Aphorisms in Prose) and:
“Reason has rulership only over what is living; the world that
has already come about, with which geognosy concerns itself,
is dead.” (Ibid.)
The
organism confronts us in nature in two main forms: as plant
and as animal, in a different way in each. The plant differs
from the animal in its lack of any real inner life.
This last manifests in the animal as sensation, arbitrary
movement, etc. The plant has no such soul principle. It still
consists entirely in its externality, in its form. By
determining its life, as it were, out of one point, that
entelechical principle confronts us in the plant in such a way
that all its individual organs are formed according to the
same developmental principle. The entelechy manifests here as
the developmental force of the individual organs. These last
are all fashioned according to one and the same developmental
type; they manifest as modifications of one basic
organ, as a repetition of this organ at different levels of
development. What makes the plant into a plant, a certain
form-creating force, is at work in every organ in the same
way. Every organ appears therefore as identical to all
the others and also to the whole plant. Goethe expresses this
as follows: “I have realized, namely, that in that organ of
the plant which we are usually accustomed to address as
‘leaf,’ the true Proteus lies hidden that can conceal and
reveal itself in every formation. Anyway you look at it, the
plant is always only leaf, so inseparably joined with the
future germ (Keim) that one cannot think the one
without the other.” (Italian Journey) Thus the plant
appears, as it were, composed of nothing but individual
plants, as a complex individual consisting in turn of simpler
ones. The development of the plant progresses therefore from
level to level and forms organs; each organ is identical to
every other, i.e., similar in formative principle, different
in appearance. The inner unity spreads itself out, as it were,
in the plant; it expresses itself in manifoldness, loses
itself in this manifoldness in such a way that it does not
gain — as the animal does, as we will see later — a concrete
existence which is endowed with a certain independence and
which, as a center of life, confronts the manifoldness of the
organs and uses them as mediators with the outer world.
The
question now arises: What brings about that difference in the
appearance of plant organs which, according to their inner
principle, are identical? How is it possible for developmental
laws that all work according to one formative principle
to bring forth at one time a leaf and at another a petal? In
the case of plant life, which lies entirely in the realm of
the external, this differentiation can also be based only upon
external, i.e., spatial, factors. Goethe regards an
alternating expansion and contraction as just such external
factors. As the entelechical principle of plant life, working
out from one point, comes into existence, it manifests itself
as something spatial; the formative forces work in space. They
create organs with definite spatial forms. Now these forces
either concentrate themselves, they strive to come together,
as it were, into one single point (this is the stage of
contraction); or they spread themselves out, unfold
themselves, seek in a certain way to distance themselves from
each other (this is the stage of expansion). In the whole life
of the plant, three expansions alternate with three
contractions. Everything that enters as differentiation into
the plant's formative forces which in their essential nature
are identical — stems from this alternating expansion and
contraction. At first the whole plant, in all its potential,
rests, drawn together into one point, in the
|
Click image for large view |
|
seed
(a). It then comes forth and unfolds itself, spreads itself
out in leaf-formation (c). The formative forces thrust
themselves apart more and more; therefore the lower leaves
appear still raw, compact (cc'); the further up the stem they
are, the more ribbed and indented they become. What formerly
was still pressing together now separates (leaf d and e). What
earlier stood at successive intervals (zz') from each other
appears again in one point of the stem (w) in the calyx (f).
This is the second contraction. In the corolla, an unfolding,
a spreading out, occurs again. Compared with the
sepals, the petals (g) are finer and more delicate, which can
only be due to a lesser intensity at one point, i.e., be due
to a greater extension of the formative forces. The next
contraction occurs in the reproductive organs (stamens (h),
and pistil (i)), after which a new expansion takes place in
the fruiting (k). In the seed (a) that emerges from the fruit,
the whole being of the plant again appears contracted to a
point. [ 37 ]
The
whole plant represents only an unfolding, a realization, of
what rests in the bud or in the seed as potentiality. Bud and
seed need only the appropriate external influences in order to
become fully developed plant forms. The only difference
between bud and seed is that the latter has the earth directly
as the basis of its unfolding, whereas the former generally
represents a plant formation upon the plant itself. The seed
represents a plant individuality of a higher kind, or, if you
will, a whole cycle of plant forms. With the forming of every
bud, the plant begins a new stage of its life, as it were; it
regenerates itself, concentrates its forces in order to unfold
them again anew. The forming of a bud is therefore an
interruption of vegetation. The plant's life can contract
itself into a bud when the conditions for actual real life are
lacking, in order then to unfold itself anew when such
conditions do occur. The interruption of vegetation in winter
is based on this. Goethe says about this: “It is very
interesting to observe how a vegetation works that is actively
continued and uninterrupted by severe cold; here there are no
buds, and one only learns now to comprehend what a bud is.”
[ 38 ] What lies hidden in
the bud where we are is open to the day there; what lies
within the bud, therefore, is true plant life; only the
conditions for its unfolding are lacking.
Goethe's concept of alternating expansion and
contraction has met with especially strong opposition. All the
attacks on it, however, originate from a misunderstanding. One
believes that these concepts could be valid only if a physical
cause could be found for them, only if one could demonstrate a
way of working of the laws at work in the plant from which
such expansion and contraction could proceed. This only shows
that one is setting the matter down on its tip instead of its
base. There is not something there that causes the contraction
and expansion; on the contrary, everything else is the result
of these; they cause a progressive metamorphosis from stage to
stage. One is just not able to picture the concept in its own
characteristic form, in its intuitive form; one requires that
the concept represent the result of an external process. One
can only think of expansion and contraction as caused and not
as causing. Goethe does not look upon expansion and
contraction as resulting from the nature of the
inorganic processes occurring in the plant; rather he regards
them as the way that inner entelechical principle shapes
itself. He could therefore not view them as a sum, as a
drawing together, of sense-perceptible processes and deduce
them from such processes, but rather had to see them as
proceeding from the inner unified principle itself.
The
plant's life is maintained by metabolism. With respect to
this, an essential difference sets in between those organs
closer to the root — i.e., to that organ which sees to the
taking in of nourishment from the earth — and those organs
that receive the nourishment which has already passed through
the other organs. The former appear directly dependent upon
their external inorganic environment; the latter, on the other
hand, upon the organic parts that precede them. Each
subsequent organ thus receives a nourishment prepared, as it
were, for it by the preceding organ. Nature progresses from
seed to fruit through a series of stages in such a way that
what follows appears as the result of what precedes. And
Goethe calls this progressing a progressing upon a
spiritual ladder. Nothing more than what we have indicated
lies in his words, “that an upper node — through the fact that
it arises out of the preceding one and receives its sap
indirectly through it — must receive its sap in a more refined
and more filtered state, must also enjoy the effects of what
the leaves have done with the sap in the meantime, must
develop itself more finely and bring a finer sap to its leaves
and buds.” All these things become comprehensible when one
applies to them the meaning intended by Goethe.
The
ideas presented here are the elements inherent in the being of
the archetypal plant — inherent in a way that conforms, in
fact, only to this archetypal plant itself, and not as these
elements manifest in any given plant where they no longer
conform to their original state but rather to external
conditions.
Something different occurs now, to be sure, in
animal life. Life does not lose itself here in its external
features, but rather separates itself, detaches itself from
its corporeality and uses its corporeal manifestation only as
a tool. It no longer expresses itself as the mere ability to
shape an organism from within outward, but rather expresses
itself within an organism as something that is still there
besides the organism, as its ruling power. The animal appears
as a self-contained world, a microcosm in a much higher sense
than the plant. It has a centre that each organ serves.
Thus is every mouth adept at grasping the
food That is right for the body, be now weak and
toothless The jaw, or mighty with teeth; in every
instance An adept organ conveys food to each
member. Also every foot does move — be it long or a short
one — All harmonious to the sense and need of the
creature.
In
the case of the plant, the whole plant is in every organ, but
the life principle exists nowhere as a particular center; the
identity of the organs lies in their being formed according to
the same laws. In the case of the animal, every organ appears
as coming from that center; the center shapes all organs in
accordance with its own nature. The form of the animal is
therefore the basis for its external existence. This form,
however, is determined from within. The way an animal lives
must therefore take its direction from those inner formative
principles. On the other hand, the inner development in itself
is unrestricted, free; within certain limits, it can adapt
itself to outer influences; but this development is still
determined by the inner nature of the typus and not by
mechanical influences from outside. Adaptation cannot
therefore go so far as to make an organism seem to be only a
product of the outer world. Its development is restricted to
certain limits.
These limits no god can extend; nature honors
them; For only thus restricted was ever the perfect
possible.
If
every animal being existed only in accordance with the
principles lying within the archetypal animal, then they would
all be alike. But the animal organism members itself into a
number of organ systems, each of which can arrive at a
definite degree of development. This is the basis now for a
diverse evolution. Equally valid among the others as idea, one
system can nevertheless push itself forward to a particular
degree; it can use for itself the supply of formative forces
lying within the animal organism and can deprive the other
organs of it. The animal will thus appear as particularly
developed in the direction of that organ system. Another
animal will appear as developed in another direction. Herein
lies the possibility for the differentiation of the archetypal
organism in its transition to the phenomenal realm in genera
and species.
The
real (factual) causes of this differentiation, however, are
still not yet given thereby. Here adaptation and the
struggle for existence come into their own right — the
former causing the organism to shape itself in accordance with
the outer conditions surrounding it, the latter working in
such a way that only those entities survive that are best
adapted to existing conditions. Adaptation and the struggle
for existence, however, could have absolutely no effect upon
the organism if the constituting principle of the organism
were not of such a kind that — while continuously maintaining
its inner unity — it can take on the most manifold forms. The
relationship of outer formative forces to this principle
should in no way be regarded as one in which, for example, the
former determine the latter in the same way one inorganic
entity determines another. The outer conditions are, to be
sure, the stimulus for the typus to develop in a
certain form; but this form itself cannot be derived from the
outer determining factors, but only from the inner principle.
In explaining the form, one should always seek the outer
factors, but one should not regard the form itself as
resulting from them. Goethe would have rejected the
derivation of the developmental forms of an organism from the
surrounding outer world through mere causality, just as much
as he rejected the teleological principle according to which
the form of an organ is traced back to an external purpose it
is to serve.
In
the case of those organ systems of an animal in which what
matters is more the external aspect of the structure — in the
bones, for example — there that law which we saw in the plants
appears again, as in the forming of the skull bones. Goethe's
gift for recognizing the inner lawfulness in purely external
forms manifests here quite especially.
The
difference between plant and animal established by these views
of Goethe might seem meaningless in face of the fact that
modern science has grounds for justifiable doubt that there is
any definite borderline between plant and animal. Goethe,
however, was already aware of the impossibility of setting up
any such borderline. In spite of this, there are specific
definitions of plant and animal. This is connected with
Goethe's whole view of nature. He assumes absolutely nothing
constant, fixed, in the phenomenal realm; for in this
realm everything fluctuates in continuous motion. But the
essential being of a thing, which can be held fast in a
concept, cannot be derived from the fluctuating forms, but
rather from certain intermediary stages at which this
being can be observed. For Goethe's view, it is quite natural
that one set up specific definitions and that these are
nevertheless not held to in one's experience of certain
transitional forms. In fact, he sees precisely in this the
mobile life of nature.
With these ideas, Goethe established the
theoretical foundations of organic science. He found the
essential being of the organism. One can easily fail to
recognize this if one demands that the typus, that
self-constituted principle (entelechy), itself be explained by
something else. But this is an unfounded demand, because the
typus, held fast in its intuitive form, explains
itself. For anyone who has grasped that “forming of itself in
accordance with itself” of the entelechical principle, this
constitutes the solution of the riddle of life. Any other
solution is impossible, because this solution is the essential
being of the thing itself. If Darwinism has to presuppose an
archetypal organism, then one can say of Goethe that he
discovered the essential being of that archetypal organism.
[ 39 ] It is Goethe who
broke with the mere juxtaposing of genera and species, and who
undertook a regeneration of organic science in accordance with
the essential being of the organism. Whereas the systems
before Goethe needed just as many different concepts (ideas)
as there were outwardly different species for which no
intermediary existed, Goethe maintained that in idea all
organisms are alike, that they are different only in their
manifestation; and he explained why they are so. With this,
the philosophical foundation for a scientific system of
organisms was created. It was then only a matter of
implementing this system. It would have to be shown how all
real organisms are only manifestations of an idea, and
how they manifest themselves in a given case.
The
great deed thus accomplished for science was also widely
acknowledged by those more educated in the field. The younger
d'Alton writes to Goethe on July 6, 1827: “I would regard it
as my greatest reward if Your Excellency, whom natural science
has to thank not only for a total transformation through
magnificent perspectives and new views in botany, but also
for many first-rate contributions to the field of osteology,
should recognize in the accompanying pages an endeavor worthy
of praise.” Nees von Esenbeck, on June 24, 1820, wrote: “In
your book, which you called An Attempt to Explain the
Metamorphosis of Plants, the plant has spoken about itself
among us for the first time, and, in this beautiful
anthropomorphism, also captivated me while I was still young.”
And finally Voigt, on June 6, 1831: “With lively interest and
humble thanks I have received your little book on
metamorphosis, which now so obligingly includes me
historically also as one of the early adherents of this
theory. It is strange: one is fairer toward animal
metamorphosis — I do not mean the old metamorphosis of the
insects, but rather the new kind about the vertebrae — than
toward plant metamorphosis. Apart from the plagiarisms and
misuses, the silent recognition of animal metamorphosis may
rest on the belief that one was risking less there.
For, in the skeleton the separate bones remain ever the same,
whereas in botany, metamorphosis threatens to topple the whole
terminology and consequently the determining of
species, and there weak people are afraid, because they do
not know where something like that might lead.” Here there is
complete understanding for Goethe's ideas. The awareness is
there that a new way of viewing what is individual must take
place; and the new systematics, the study of particulars,
should only first proceed then from this new view. The
self-supporting typus contains the possibility of
assuming endlessly manifold forms as it enters into
manifestation; and these forms are the object of our sense
perception, are the genera and species of the organism living
in space and time. Insofar as our spirit apprehends that
general idea, the typus, it has grasped the whole realm
of organisms in all its unity. When now our spirit
beholds the development of the typus in each
particular form of manifestation, this form becomes
comprehensible to it; this form appears to our spirit as one
of the stages, one of the metamorphoses, in which the
typus realizes itself. And the nature of the
systematics to be founded by Goethe was to consist in
demonstrating these different stages. In the animal, as well
as in the plant realm, there holds sway an ascending
evolutionary sequence; organisms are divided into highly
developed and undeveloped ones. How is this possible? It is
characteristic of the ideal form of the typus of the
organisms, in fact, that it consists of spatial and temporal
elements. For this reason, it also appeared to Goethe as a
sensible-supersensible form. It contains spatial
temporal forms as ideal perception (intuitive). When the
typus now enters into manifestation, the truly (no
longer intuitive) sense-perceptible form can correspond fully
to that ideal form or not; the typus can come to its
full development or not. The lower organisms are indeed lower
through the fact that their form of manifestation does not
fully correspond with the organic typus. The more that
outer manifestation and organic typus coincide in a
given entity, the more highly developed it is. This is the
objective basis of an ascending evolutionary sequence. It is
the task of any systematics to demonstrate this relationship
with respect to the form of every organism. In arriving at the
typus, the archetypal organism, however, no account can
be taken of this; in arriving at the typus it can only
be a matter of finding a form that represents the most perfect
expression of the typus. Goethe's archetypal plant is
meant to provide such a form.
One
has reproached Goethe for taking no account of the world of
cryptogamia in arriving at his typus. We have indicated
earlier that this could only have been so out of the fullest
consciousness, since he did occupy himself also with the study
of these plants. This does have its objective basis, however.
The cryptogamia are in fact those plants in which the
archetypal plant only comes to expression in a highly one
sided way; they represent the idea of the plant in a one-sided
sense-perceptible form. They can be judged according to the
idea thus set up; but this idea itself only bursts forth fully
in the phanerogamia.
But
what is to be said here is that Goethe never accomplished this
implementation of his basic thought, that he entered too
little into the realm of the particular. Therefore all his
works remain fragmentary. His intention of also shedding light
here is shown by his words in the Italian Journey
(September 27, 1786) to the effect that it will be possible,
with the help of his ideas, “truly to determine genera and
species, which until now has occurred in a very arbitrary way,
it seems to me.” He did not carry out this intention, did not
make a specific presentation of the connection of his general
thoughts to the realm of the particular, to the reality of the
individual forms. This he himself regarded as a deficiency in
his fragments; with respect to this he writes to Soret von de
Candolle on June 28, 1828: “It is also becoming more and more
clear to me how he regards my intentions, in which I am
persisting and which, in my short essay on metamorphosis,
are stated definitely enough, it is true, but whose connection
with botany based on perception does not emerge clearly
enough, as I have known for a long time.” This is
certainly also the reason why Goethe's views were so
misunderstood; they were misunderstood only because they were
not understood at all.
In
Goethe's concepts we also gain an ideal explanation for the
fact, discovered by Darwin and Haeckel, that the developmental
history of the individual represents a repetition of the
history of the race. For, what Haeckel puts forward here
cannot after all be taken for anything more than an
unexplained fact. It is the fact that every individual entity
passes, in a shortened form, through all those stages of
development that paleontology also shows us as separate
organic forms. Haeckel and his followers explain this by the
law of heredity. But heredity is itself nothing other than an
abbreviated expression for the fact just mentioned. The
explanation for it is that those forms, as well as those of
the individual, are the manifest forms of one and the same
archetypal image that, in successive epochs, brings to
unfoldment the formative forces lying within this image as
potentiality. Every higher entity is indeed more perfect
through the fact that, through the favorable influences of its
environment, it is not hindered in the completely free
unfolding of itself in accordance with its inner nature. If,
on the other hand, because of certain influences, the
individual is compelled to remain at a lower stage, then only
some of its inner forces come to manifestation, and then that
which is only a part of a whole in a more highly developed
individual is this individual's whole. And in this way the
higher organism appears in its development as composed of the
lower organisms, or too the lower organisms appear in their
development as parts of the higher one. In the development of
a higher animal, we must therefore also see again the
development of all the lower ones (biogenetic law). Just as
the physicist is not satisfied with merely stating and
describing-facts, but also seeks out their laws — i.e.,
the concepts of the phenomena — so, for the person who wants
to penetrate into the nature of organic entities, it also does
not suffice for him merely to cite the facts of kinship,
heredity, struggle for existence, etc.; but rather he wants to
know the ideas underlying these things. We find this striving
in Goethe. What Kepler's three laws are for the physicist,
Goethe's ideas of the typus are for the organic
scientist. Without them, the world is a mere labyrinth of
facts for us. This has often been misunderstood. One declares
that the concept of metamorphosis in Goethe's sense is merely
a picture that basically occurs only in our intellect
through abstraction. That Goethe was not clear about the fact
that the concept of the transformation of leaves into flower
organs makes sense only if the latter, the stamens, for
example, were once real leaves. However, this turns Goethe's
view upside down. A sense-perceptible organ is turned into a
principally primary one and the other organ is then derived
from it in a sense-perceptible way. Goethe never meant it this
way. For him, what is first in time is absolutely not also
first with respect to the idea, to the principle. It is not
because the stamens were once true leaves that they are now
related to the leaves; no, but rather because they are related
ideally, in accordance with their inner nature, they appeared
at one time as true leaves. The sense-perceptible
transformation is only the result of the ideal relatedness and
not the other way around. Today, it is an established
empirical fact that all the lateral organs of the plant are
identical; but why does one call them identical? According to
Schleiden, because these all develop on the axis in
such a way that they are pushed forth as lateral
protuberances, in such a way that lateral cell formation
remains only on the original body and that no new cells form
on the tip that is formed first. This is a purely external
relatedness, and one considers the idea of identity to be the
result of this. Again the matter is otherwise for Goethe. For
him the lateral organs are identical in their idea, in their
inner being; therefore they also manifest outwardly as
identical formations. For him, sense-perceptible relatedness
is a result of inner, ideal relatedness. The Goethean
conception differs from the materialistic one in the way it
poses its questions; the two do not contradict one another;
they complement one another. Goethe's ideas provide the
foundation for the other view. Goethe's ideas are not merely a
poetic foreshadowing of later discoveries but rather
independent principle discoveries that have not by far been
valued enough and upon which natural science will still draw
for a long time. Even when the empirical facts that he used
shall have been far surpassed, or in part even disproven, by
more exact and detailed research. still the ideas he set up
are fundamental once and for all for organic science, because
they are independent of those empirical facts. Just as,
according to Kepler's laws, every newly discovered planet must
revolve around its star, so must every process in organic
nature occur according to Goethe's ideas. Long before Kepler
and Copernicus, people saw the occurrences in the starry
heavens. These two first found the laws. Long before Goethe,
people observed the realm of organic nature; Goethe found its
laws. Goethe is the Copernicus and Kepler of the organic
world.
One
can also clarify for oneself the nature of the Goethean theory
in the following way. Besides ordinary empirical mechanics,
which only collects the facts, there is also a rational
mechanics, which, from the inner nature of the basic
mechanical principles, deduces the a priori laws as
necessary ones. As empirical mechanics relates to rational
mechanics, so the theories of Darwin, Haeckel, etc., relate to
the rational organic science of Goethe. About this aspect of
his theory, Goethe was not at once clear from the beginning.
Later, to be sure, he expressed it quite emphatically. When he
writes to Heinrich Wilhelm Ferdinand Wackenroder, on January
21, 1832: “Continue to acquaint me with everything that
interests you; it will connect somewhere with my
reflections,” he means by this only that he has found the
basic principles of organic science from which everything else
must be derived. At an earlier time, however, this all worked
unconsciously in his spirit and he just treated the facts
according to it. [ 40 ] It first became
objectively clear to him through that first scientific
conversation with Schiller which we will describe later.
Schiller recognized right away the ideal nature of Goethe's
archetypal plant and declared that no reality could be
consistent with such a plant. This stimulated Goethe to think
about the relationship of what he called “typus” to
empirical reality. He encountered a problem here that belongs
to the most significant problems of all human investigation:
the problem of the relationship between idea and reality,
between thinking and experience. This became ever
clearer to him: No one single empirical object corresponds
entirely to his typus; no entity of nature was
identical to it. The content of the typus concept
cannot therefore stem from the sense world as such,
even though it is won in the encounter with the sense
world. Its content must therefore lie within the typus
itself; the idea of the archetypal entity could only be of a
kind which, by virtue of a necessity lying within itself,
develops a content out of itself that then in another form —
in the form of a perception — manifests within the phenomenal
world. it is interesting in this regard to see how Goethe
himself, when meeting empirical natural scientists. stood up
for the rights of experience and for keeping idea and
object strictly separated. In 1786, Sömmerring sends him a
book in which Sömmerring makes an attempt to discover the seat
of the soul. In a letter that he sends to Sömmerring on August
28, 1796, Goethe finds that Sömmerring has woven too much
metaphysics into his views; an idea about objects of
experience has no justification if it goes beyond these,
if it is not founded in the being of the object itself. With
objects of experience, the idea is an organ for grasping, in
its necessary interconnection, that which otherwise would be
merely perceived in a blind juxtaposition and succession. But,
from the fact that the idea is not allowed to bring anything
new to the object, it follows that the object itself, in its
own essential being, is something ideal and that empirical
reality must have two sides: one, by which it is particular,
individual, and the other by which it is ideal-general.
Association with contemporary philosophers and
the reading of their works led Goethe to many points of view
in this respect. Schelling's work On the World-Soul
[ 41 ] and his Sketch
of a System of Natural Philosophy [ 42 ] as well as
Steffen's Basic Features of a Philosophical Natural
Science [ 43 ] were fruitful for
him. Also a great deal was talked through with Hegel. These
stimuli finally led him to take up Kant again, with whom
Goethe had already once occupied himself at Schiller's
instigation. In 1817 (see his Annals) he takes a
historical look at Kant's influence upon his ideas on nature
and natural things. To these reflections, going to the core of
science, we owe the following essays:
Fortunate Event (Glückliches
Ereignis) Power to Judge in Beholding (Anschauende
Urteilskraft) Reflection and Devotion (Bedenken und
Ergebung) Formative Impulse
(Bildungstrieb) Apologies for the Undertaking
(Das Unternehmen wird entschuldigt) The Purpose
Introduced (Die Absicht eingeleitet) The Content
Prefaced (Der Inhalt bevorwortet) History of My
Botanical Studies (Geschichte meines botanischen
Studiums) How the Essay on the Metamorphosis of the
Plants Arose (Entstehen des Aufsatzes über Metamorphose der
Pflanzen)
All
these essays express the thought already indicated above, that
every object has two sides: the direct one of its
manifestation (form of manifestation), and the second one that
contains its being. In this way, Goethe arrives at the
only satisfactory view of nature, which establishes the one
truly objective method. If a theory regards the ideas as
something foreign to the object itself, as something merely
subjective, then it cannot profess to be truly objective if it
ever uses the idea at all. But Goethe can maintain that he
adds nothing to the objects that does not already lie in the
objects themselves.
Goethe also pursued the detailed factual aspects
of those branches of science to which his ideas were related.
In 1795, he attended lectures by Loder on the ligaments;
during this period, he did not at all lose sight of anatomy
and physiology, which seems all the more important since it
was precisely then that he was writing his lectures on
osteology. In 1796 attempts were made to grow plants in
darkness and under coloured glass. Later on, the metamorphosis
of insects was also investigated.
A
further stimulus came from the philologist F.A. Wolff who drew
Goethe's attention to his namesake Wolff who, in his
Theoria Generationis, had already expressed ideas in
1759 that were similar to those of Goethe on the metamorphosis
of the plants. Goethe was moved by this fact to concern
himself more deeply with Wolff, which he did in 1807; he
discovered later, however, that Wolff, with all his acuity,
was not yet clear on precisely the main points. Wolff did not
yet know the typus as something non-sense-perceptible,
as something that develops its content merely out of inner
necessity. He still regarded the plant as an external,
mechanical complex of individual details.
Goethe's exchanges with his many scientist
friends, as well as the joy of having found recognition and
imitation of his endeavors among many kindred spirits, led
Goethe to the thought, in 1807, of publishing the fragments of
his natural-scientific studies that he had held back until
then. He gradually abandoned his intention of writing a more
comprehensive natural-scientific work. But the individual
essays did not yet reach publication in 1807. His interest in
the colour theory pushed morphology into the background again
for a time. The first booklet of these essays first appeared
in 1817. By 1824, two volumes of these essays had appeared,
the first in four booklets, the second in two. Besides the
essays on Goethe's own views, we also find here discussions of
significant literary publications in the realm of morphology,
and also treatises of other scholars, whose presentations,
however, are always complementary to Goethe's interpretation
of nature.
On
yet two further occasions, Goethe was challenged to occupy
himself more intensively with natural-scientific matters. Both
of these involved significant literary publications — in the
realm of science — that related most deeply to his own
strivings. On the first occasion, the stimulus was given by
the studies of the botanist Martius on the spiral tendency in
plants, on the second occasion, by a natural-scientific
dispute in the French Academy of Sciences.
Martius saw plant form, in its development, as
comprised of a spiral and a vertical tendency. The vertical
tendency brings about growth in the direction of the root and
stem; the spiral tendency brings about the spreading out of
leaves, blossoms, etc. Goethe saw in this thought only an
elaboration of ideas he had already set down in 1790 in his
book on metamorphosis, but here focusing more on spatial
elements (vertical, spiral). For proof of this assertion, we
refer you to our comments on Goethe's essay, On the Spiral
Tendency of Vegetation, [ 44 ] from which the fact
emerges that Goethe, in this essay, does not bring forward
anything essentially new with respect to his earlier ideas. We
want to direct this statement particularly to those who assert
that there is evident here, in fact, a retrogression of Goethe
from his earlier clear views back into the “deepest depths of
mysticism.”
Even at a most advanced age (1830-32), Goethe
still wrote two essays on the dispute between the two French
natural scientists, Cuvier and Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire. In
these essays we find yet once more, in striking conciseness, a
synthesis of the principles of Goethe's view of nature.
Cuvier was altogether an empiricist of the old
school of natural science. For each species of animal he
sought a particular corresponding concept. He believed he had
to take up into the conceptual edifice of his system of
organic nature as many individual types as there are animal
species present in nature. But for him the individual types
stood there side by side without any mediation. What he did
not take into consideration is this. Our need for knowledge is
not satisfied with the particular as such in the way it
approaches us directly as phenomenon. But since we approach an
entity of the sense world with no other intention, in fact,
than of knowing it, we should not assume that the reason we
declare ourselves unsatisfied with the particular as such is
to be found in the nature of our ability to know. On the
contrary, the reason must lie within the object itself. The
essential being of the particular itself, in fact, by no means
consists only in this, its particularness; it presses, in
order to be understood, toward a kind of being that is not
particular, but rather, general (ein Allgemeines). This
ideal-general is the actual being — the essence of every
particular entity. Only one side of the existence of a
particular entity lies in its particularness; the other side
is the general — the typus (see Goethe's Aphorisms
in Prose). This is how it is to be understood when the
particular is spoken of as a form of the general. Since the
ideal-general is therefore the actual being, the content, of
the particular, it is impossible for the ideal-general to be
derived, abstracted, from the particular. Since it has nowhere
from which to borrow its content, it must give this content to
itself. The typical-general is therefore of such a nature
that, in it, content and form are identical. But it can
therefore also be grasped only as a whole, independent of what
is individual. Science has the task with every particular
entity of showing how, according to the entity's essential
being, the entity subordinates itself to the ideal-general.
Through this the particular kinds of existence enter
the stage of mutually determining and depending upon each
other. What otherwise can be perceived only as
spatial-temporal juxtaposition and succession is now seen in
necessary interconnection. But Cuvier wouldn't hear of
any such view. This view, on the other hand, was the one held
by Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire. This is actually the aspect that
aroused Goethe's interest in this dispute. The matter has
often been misrepresented because one saw the facts, through
the glasses of most modern views, in a completely different
light than that in which they appear if one approaches them
without preconceptions. Geoffroy referred not only to his own
research, but also to a number of German scientists of like
mind, among whom Goethe is also named.
Goethe's interest in this matter was
extraordinary. He was extremely happy to find a colleague in
Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire: “Now Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire is also
definitely on our side and with him all his significant
students and adherents in France This event is of
inconceivably great value to me, and I am right to jubilate
about the final victory of something to which I have dedicated
my life and which is pre-eminently also my own,” he says to
Eckermann on August 2, 1830. It is altogether a strange
phenomenon that in Germany Goethe's research found a response
only among philosophers and but little among natural
scientists, whereas the response in France was more
significant among the latter. De Candolle gave Goethe's theory
of metamorphosis his closest attention and treated botany
generally in a way that was not far from Goethean views. Also,
Goethe's Metamorphosis had already been translated into
French by F. de Gingins-Lassaraz. Under such conditions,
Goethe could definitely hope that a translation of his
botanical writings into French, carried out with his
collaboration, would not fall on barren ground. Such a
translation was then provided in 1831, with Goethe's
continuous assistance, by Friedrich Jakob Soret. It contained
that first Attempt of 1790, the history of Goethe's
botanical studies, and the effect of his theories upon his
contemporaries, as well as something about de Candolle, — in
French, with German on the opposite page.
|