Gilles Deleuze, an important figure in
post-war French philosophy, began his career with a number of
idiosyncratic yet rigorous historical studies of figures
outside of the continental tradition in vogue at the time,
before writing some of the more infamous texts of the period,
in particular, Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand
Plateaus. These texts collaborative works with radical
psychoanalyst Félix Guattari. Deleuze is a key figure in what
is known as 'postmodern' thought. Considering himself an
empiricist and a vitalist, his body of work, which rests upon
concepts such as multiplicity, constructivism, difference and
desire, stands at a substantial remove from the main
traditions of 20th century Continental thought. His thought
locates him as an influential figure in present-day
considerations of society, creativity and subjectivity.
Deleuze also published widely on literature, psychoanalysis
and art.
Table of Contents
(Clicking on the links below will take you to those parts of
this article)
1.
Biography
Gilles Deleuze (1925-1995) was born in the 17th
arrondisment of Paris, a district that, excepting periods in
his youth, he lived in for the whole of his life. He was the
son of an conservative, anti-Semitic engineer, a veteran of
World War I. Deleuze's brother was arrested by Germans during
the Nazi occupation of France for alleged resistance
activities, and died on the way to Auschwitz.
Due to his families' lack of money, Deleuze was schooled at
a public school before the war. When the Germans invaded
France, Deleuze was on vacation in Normandy and spent a year
being schooled there. In Normandy, he was inspired by a
teacher, under whose influence he read Gide, Baudelaire and
others, becoming for the first time interested in his studies.
In a late interview, he states that after this experience, he
never had any trouble academically. After returning to Paris
and finishing his high school education, Deleuze attended the
Lycée Henri IV, where he did his kâgne, an intensive year of
study for students of promise, in 1945, and then studied
philosophy at the Sorbonne with figures such as Jean Hippolyte
and Georges Canguilheim. He passed his agrégation in 1948,
necessary for entry into the teaching profession, and taught
in a number of high schools until 1956. In this year, he also
married Denise Paul "Fanny" Grandjouan, a French translator of
D.H. Lawrence. His first book, Empiricism and
Subjectivity, on David Hume, was published in 1953, when
he was 28.
Over the next ten years, Deleuze held a number of assistant
teaching positions in French universities, publishing his
important text on Nietzsche (Nietzsche and Philosophy)
in 1962. It was also around this time that he met Michel
Foucault, with whom he had a long and important friendship.
When Foucault died, Deleuze dedicated a book-length study to
his work (Foucault 1986). In 1968, Deleuze's doctoral
thesis, comprising of Difference and Repetition and
Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza were published.
This was also the period of the first major incidence of
pulmonary illness that would plague Deleuze for the rest of
his life.
In 1969, Deleuze took up a teaching post at the
'experimental' University of Paris VII, where he taught until
his retirement in 1987. In the same year, he met Félix
Guattari, with whom he wrote a number of influential texts,
notably the two volumes of Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, Anti-Oedipus (1972) and A
Thousand Plateaus (1980). These texts were considered by
many (including Deleuze) to be an expression in part of the
political ferment in France during May 1968. During the
seventies, Deleuze was politically active in a number of
causes, including membership in the Groupe d'information
sur les prisons (formed, with others, by Michel Foucault),
and had an engaged concern with homosexual rights and the
Palestinian liberation movement.
In the eighties, Deleuze wrote a number of books on cinema
(the influential studies The Movement-Image (1983) and
The Time-Image (1985)) and on painting (Francis
Bacon (1981)). Deleuze's final collaboration with
Guattari, What is Philosophy?, was published in 1991
(Guattari died in 1992).
Deleuze's last book, a collection of essays on literature
and related philosophical questions, Essays Critical and
Clinical, was published in 1993. Deleuze's pulmonary
illness, by 1993, had confined him quite severely, even making
it difficult for him to write. He took his own life on
November 4th, 1995.
2. The History Of Philosophy
Deleuze's whole intellectual trajectory can be traced by
his shifting relationship to the history of philosophy. While
in later years, he became quite critical of both the style of
thought implied in narrow reproductions of past thinkers and
the institutional pressures to think on this basis, Deleuze
never lost any enthusiasm for writing books about other
philosophers, if in a new way. Most of his publications
contain the name of another philosopher as part of the title:
Hume, Kant, Spinoza, Nietzsche, Bergson, Leibniz, Foucault.
Deleuze expresses two main problems with the traditional
style and institutional location of the history of philosophy.
The first concerns a politics of the tradition:
The history of philosophy has always been the agent of
power in philosophy, and even in thought. It has played the
repressors role: how can you think without having read Plato,
Descartes, Kant and Heidegger, and so-and-so's book about
them? A formidable school of intimidation which manufactures
specialists in thought - but which also makes those who stay
outside conform all the more to this specialism which they
despise. An image of thought called philosophy has been formed
historically and it effectively stops people from
thinking. (D 13)
This hegemony of thought recurrently comes under attack
later in Deleuze's career, notably in What is
Philosophy? This criticism also sits well with a general
theme throughout his writings, which is the immediate
politicisation of all thought. Philosophy and its history is
not separated from the fortunes of the wider world, for
Deleuze, but intimately linked to it, and to the forces at
work there.
The second criticism directed at the traditional style of
history of philosophy, the construction of specialists and
expertise, leads directly to the foremost positive aspect of
Deleuze's particular method: "What we should in fact do, is
stop allowing philosophers to reflect 'on' things. The
philosopher creates, he doesn't reflect." (N122) And this
creation, with regard to other writers, takes the form of a
portrait:
The history of philosophy isn't a particularly
reflective discipline. It's rather like portraiture in
painting. Producing mental, conceptual portraits. As in
painting, you have to create a likeness, but in a different
material: the likeness is something you have to produce,
rather than a way of reproducing anything (which comes down to
just repeating what a philosopher says). (N 136)
Perhaps such a method does not seem extremely creative, or
perhaps only in a relatively passive sense. For Deleuze,
however, the history of philosophy also embraces a much more
active, constructive sense. Each reading of a philosopher, an
artist, a writer should be undertaken, Deleuze tells us, in
order to provide an impetus for creating new concepts that do
not pre-exist (DR vii).
Thus the works that Deleuze studies are seen by him as
inspirational, but also as a resource, from which the
philosopher can gather the concepts that seem the most useful
and give them a new life, along with the force to develop new,
non-preexistent concepts.
In an important sense, Deleuze's whole modus operandi is
based in this revaluation of the role of other thinkers, and
the means by which one can use them: each of his books either
centers around one philosopher, or derives much of its texture
from references to others. In any case, new concepts are
derived from others' works, or old ones are recreated or
'awakened', and put to a new service.
a. Two examples: Kant and Leibniz
Deleuze's book on Kant, his third publication (1963) in
general conforms with the standards of an academic
philosophical study. Aside from its surprising breadth,
covering as it does all three of Kant's Critiques in a
slender volume, it focuses on a problem that is clearly of
concern to both Kant himself and the traditional reading of
his work, that of the relationship between the faculties.
Deleuze himself, later reflecting on Kant's Critical
Philosophy, distinguishes it from the other, more
constructivist historical studies:
My book on Kant's different; I like it, I did it as a
book about an enemy that tries to show how his system works,
its various cogs - the tribunal of Reason, the legitimate
exercises of the faculties. (N 6)
There are, however, some distinctively creative elements
even to this apparently sober study, which reflect Deleuze's
general interests, two in particular. In this text on Kant,
these reveal themselves by way of emphasis, rather than
out-and-out creation.
The first of these is his emphasis on Kant's rejections of
transcendentality at key points in the Critiques, in
favour of a generalised pragmatism of reason. While Deleuze
himself locates in Kant the development of the concept of the
transcendental at the root of modern philosophy (DR 135), he
is quick to insist that, even as transcendental faculties in
Kant, understanding, reason and imagination act only in an
immanent fashion to achieve their own ends:
. . . the so-called transcendental method is always the
determination of an immanent employment of reason, conforming
to one of its interests. The Critique of Pure Reason thus
condemns the transcendent employment of a speculative reason
which claims to legislate by itself; the Critique of Practical
Reason condemns the transcendent employment of practical
reason which, instead of legislating by itself, lets itself be
empirically conditioned. (KCP 36-7; cf. KCP 24-5; NP 91)
Deleuze, then, insists on the critical activity of Kant's
philosophy as not only a critique of reason used wrongly, but
specifies this critique in pragmatic and empiricist terms.
The second Deleuzian feature of Kant's Critical
Philosophy is its insistence on the creative and
affirmative nature of the Critique of Judgement. This
runs counter not just to a number of Kant scholars, who
suggest that the third Critique is a defected work as a
result of Kant's age and decaying mental abilities when he
wrote it, but also other prominent French philosophers of
Deleuze's generation, notably Jean-Francois Lyotard and
Jacques Derrida, who both consider this text primarily in
terms of its aporetic nature.
Deleuze, to the contrary, insists on its central importance
to Kant's philosophy. He argues not only that there are
conflicts between the activity of the faculties, and thus
between the first two Critiques, a moot point in
reading Kant, but that the Critique of Judgement solves
this problem (already a controversial perspective) by positing
a genesis of free accord between the faculties deeper than
their conflicts. Not only are the struggles between the
faculties not insoluble: there is in fact an affirmative
creation of a resolution that does not rely upon any
transcendental faculty.
When we turn to consider a much later text, The Fold:
Leibniz and the Baroque, we find Deleuze's constructivist
practice of the history of philosophy developed to its
fullest. This text is not only a 'portrait' of Leibniz's
thought, but uses concepts drawn from it, along with new
concepts based in a philosophical 'take' on mathematics, art,
and music, to characterise the Baroque period, and indeed vice
versa. Leibniz, Deleuze argues, is the philosopher whose point
of view can be best used to understand the Baroque period, and
Baroque architecture, music and art give us a unique and
illuminating vantage point for reading Leibniz. In fact, one
of the more astonishing claims that Deleuze makes is that the
one cannot be understood properly without the other:
It is impossible to understand the Leibnizian monad, and
its light-mirror-point of view-interior decoration system, if
we do not come to terms with these elements in Baroque
architecture. (FLB 39; translation altered)
How is such a statement to be demonstrated? Instead of
claiming that in fact there is an a priori link between
Leibniz and the Baroque, Deleuze creates a new concept, and
reads both of them through it: this is the concept of the
fold. In keeping with Leibniz's theory of the monad, that the
whole universe is contained within each being, like the
Baroque church, Deleuze argues that the process of folding
constitutes the basic unit of existence. While there are
elements of the fold already in Leibniz and the architecture
and art of the period, as Deleuze points out (N 157), it gains
a new consistency and significance when used as a creative
term in this manner. Throughout the book, and later, in
Foucault, Deleuze uses the concept of the fold to
describe the nature of the human subject as the outside folded
in: an immanently political, social, embedded subject.
In addition, in The Fold, we see a remarkable
cross-section of Deleuze's whole work, expressed in a new way
through the material that he analyses. Chapters 4 and 6 give a
succinct formulation of the relationship between the event and
the subject (one of Deleuze's perennial interests), which
leads to a new formulation of the nature of sufficient reason
in line with Deleuze's concept of the virtual. We also see a
return to the question of the body that he examines with
Guattari in Capitalism and Schizophrenia. (FLB sec III:
'Having a body'), which reinstates the work of Leibniz on the
level of the material, rather than in the realm of idealism.
Deleuze thus provides a reading of Leibniz that strikes the
reader as eccentric and certainly at odds with the traditional
approach, and yet which holds to both the text (in all his
historical studies, Deleuze cites quite exhaustively), and to
the new direction that he is working in.
3. A New Empiricism
In the English preface to the Dialogues, Deleuze
writes the following:
I have always felt that I am an empiricist . . . [My
empiricism] is derived from the two characteristics by which
Whitehead defined empiricism: the abstract does not explain,
but must itself be explained; and the aim is not to rediscover
the eternal or the universal, but to find the conditions under
which something new is produced (creativeness). (D vii;
cf. N 88; WP 7)
One can see that such a definition of empiricism differs
sharply, at least apparently, from the traditional
understanding canonised by Anglo-American histories of
philosophy. Such a history would have us believe that
empiricism is above all the doctrine that whatever knowledge
that we possess is derived from the senses and the senses
alone - the well-known rejection of innate ideas. Modern views
of science embrace such a doctrine, and apply it as a tool to
derive facts about the physical world.
Deleuze's empiricism is both an extreme radicalisation and
rejection of this sense-data model: "Empiricism is by no means
. . . a simple appeal to lived experience." (DR xx; cf. PI
35). Rather, it takes a standpoint regarding the
transcendental in general. Writing of Hume, he states that, We
can now see the special ground of empiricism: . . . nothing is
ever transcendental." (ES 24) To claim that knowledge is
derived from the senses alone and not from ideas which exist
in the mind prior to experience (as is argued in a long
tradition from Plato to Descartes and beyond, lingering in the
discourse of modern science) is indeed a rejection of a
certain transcendentality of the mind, but for Deleuze, this
is only the very first moment of a radical displacement of all
transcendentals that is central in all of his work:
questioning the supremacy of reason as the a priori
privileged way of relating to the world, questioning the link
between freedom and will, attempting to abolish dualisms from
ontology, reinstating politics prior to Being.
To return to the citation from the Dialogues, there
are two aspects of Deleuze's empiricist philosophy. The first
is the rejection of all transcendentals, but the second is an
active element: for Deleuze, empiricism is always about
creating. In terms of philosophy, the creation par excellence
is the creation of concepts: "Empiricism is by no means a
reaction against concepts . . . On the contrary, it undertakes
the most insane creation of concepts ever." (DR xx) This idea
of philosophy as an empiricist creation of concepts, or
constructivism, is taken up again in What is
Philosophy?, and is present, as noted above, in all of his
historical studies of philosophers.
These two facets of empiricism are throughout Deleuze's
work, and it is in this sense that his claim about being such
a philosopher is clearly true. Deleuze primarily developed
this point of view through the texts he wrote prior to 1968,
and particularly through three other philosophers, who he
reads as empiricists in the sense mentioned: Hume, Spinoza and
Nietzsche.
a. Hume
Deleuze's first publication, Empiricism and
Subjectivity (1953) is a book about David Hume, who is
generally considered the foremost and most rigorous British
empiricist, according to the general 'sense-data' model
described above. Deleuze, however, takes Hume to be far more
radical than he is normally considered to be. While this text
very carefully reads Hume's works, especially the Treatise
of Human Nature, the portrait that emerges is quite
strikingly idiosyncratic.
On Deleuze's account, Hume is above all a philosopher of
subjectivity. His central concern is to establish the basis
upon which the subject is formed. All the well-known arguments
about habit, causation and miracles reveal a more profound
question: if there is nothing transcendental, how are we to
understand the self-aware, creative self who seems to govern
the nature that he somehow has sprung up from? Deleuze argues
then that the relation between human nature and nature is
Hume's central concern (ES 109).
Deleuze develops this argument by asserting precisely the
opposite of the traditional reading of Hume:
According to Hume, and also Kant, the principles of
knowledge are not derived from experience. But in the case of
Hume, nothing is transcendental, because these principles are
simply principles of our nature . . . (ES 111-2)
Kant proposed transcendental operations of categories in
order to make experience possible, criticising Hume for
thinking that we could have unified knowledge of an empirical
flux that we only passively receive. On Deleuze's reading,
however, Hume did not suppose that there were no unifying
processes at work, on the contrary. The difference is that for
Hume, these principles are natural; they do not rely upon the
postulation of a priori structures of experience.
The question of the subject is resolved by Hume, according
to Deleuze, by the creation of a number of key concepts:
association, belief, and the externality of relations.
Association is the principle of nature which operates by
establishing a relation between two things. The imagination is
affected by this principle to create a new unity, which can in
turn be used later on to come to conclusions about other ideas
that this unity resembles, is closely related to, or seems to
cause. If we consider the traditional example of the balls on
a pool table, the process of association allows a subject to
form a relation of causality between one ball and the next, so
that the next time one ball comes into contact with another,
an expectation that the second ball will move is created.
Thus Hume, for Deleuze, considers the mind to be a system
of associations alone, a network of tendencies (ES 25): "We
are habits, nothing but habits - the habit of saying 'I'.
Perhaps there is no more striking answer to the problem of the
Self." (ES x.) The mind, affected by the natural principle of
association, becomes human nature, from the ground up:
Empirical subjectivity is constituted in the mind under
the influence of the principles affecting it; the mind
therefore does not have the characteristics of a preexisting
subject. (ES 29)
These associations account not only for experience in the
basic sense, but up to the highest level of social and
cultural life: this is the basis for Hume's rejection of a
social contract model of society (such as Hobbes'), in favour
of convention alone. Morals, feelings, bodily comportment, all
of these elements of subjectivity are explained, not by
transcendental structures, such as Kant will propose, but the
immanent activity of association.
Once this habitual structure of the self is in place,
Deleuze suggests, the Humean concept of belief comes into
play, which is resolutely a central part of human nature. It
describes the particularly human way of going beyond the
given. When we expect the sun to come up tomorrow, we do not
do so because we know that it will, but because of a belief
based on a habit. This in turn reverses the hierarchy of
knowledge and belief, and results, for Deleuze, in a, "great
conversion of theory to practice." (PI 36) Every act of belief
is a practical application of habit, without any reference to
an a priori ability to judge. Not only is the human
being thus habitual, on Deleuze's reading, but also creative,
even in the most mundane moments of life.
Finally, Deleuze insists that one of Hume's greatest
contributions to modern philosophy is his insistence that all
relations are external to their terms: this is the essence of
Hume's anti-transcendental stance. Human nature cannot unite
itself, there is no 'I' which stands before experience, but
only moments of experience themselves, unattached and
meaningless without any necessary relation to each other. A
flash of red, a movement, a gust of wind, these elements must
be externally related to each other to create the sensation of
a tree in autumn. In the social world, this externality
attests to the always-already interested nature of life: no
relation is necessary, or governed by neutral laws, so every
relation has a localised and passional motive. The ways in
which habits are formed attests to the desires at the heart of
our social milieu.
Subjectivity, as Deleuze describes it through his reading
of Hume, is a practical, passional, empiricist concept,
immediately located at the heart of the conventional, which is
to say the social.
b. Spinoza
While Hume may not be a contentious name to link with a
deepened empiricism, Benedict de Spinoza certainly is.
Generally considered the arch-rationalist par excellence,
Spinoza is most well known for the first main thesis proposed
in his Ethics: that there is one substance, God or
Nature, and that everything that exists is merely a modulation
of this substance. His style of writing, known as the
'geometric method', is composed by propositions, proofs, and
axioms. Such a point of view hardly seems consistent with a
radical construction of concepts, and an essential pragmatism:
and yet this is what Deleuze's interpretation of Spinoza,
which has been very influential (as recent texts such as those
by Geneveive Lloyd and Moira Gatens demonstrate), argues.
Spinoza is without a doubt the philosopher most praised and
referred to by Deleuze, often with words that are rarely a
part of philosophical writing. For example:
Spinoza is, for me, the 'prince' of philosophers.
(EPS 11)
Spinoza is the Christ of philosophers, and the greatest
philosophers are hardly more than apostles who distance
themselves from or draw near to this mystery. (WP 60)
Spinoza: the absolute philosopher, whose Ethics is the
foremost book on concepts. (N 140)
Spinoza's greatness for Deleuze comes precisely from his
development of a philosophy based on the two features of
empiricism discussed above. Indeed, for Deleuze, Spinoza
combines the two things into one movement: a rejection of the
transcendental in the action of creating a plane of absolute
immanence upon which all that exists situate themselves. In
more Spinozist language, we can refer to the thesis of a
single substance instead of a plane of immanence; all bodies
(beings) are modal expressions of the one substance (SPP 122).
But not only is The Ethics for Deleuze the creation
of a plane of immanence, it is the creation of a whole regime
of new concepts that revolve around the rejection of the
transcendental in all spheres of life. The unity of the
ontological and the ethical is crucial, for Deleuze, in
understanding Spinoza, that is:
Spinoza didn't entitle his book Ontology, he's too
shrewd for that, he entitles it Ethics. Which is a way of
saying that, whatever the importance of my speculative
propositions may be, you can only judge them at the level of
the ethics that they envelope or imply [impliquer].
In short, as the title of one of Deleuze's books,
Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, indicates, the
Ethics is only understood when it is seen, at one and
the same time, to be theoretical and practical. Deleuze
considers there to be three primary theoretico-practical
points in the Ethics:
The great theories of the Ethics . . . cannot be treated
apart from the three practical theses concerning
consciousness, values and the sad passions (SPP 28)
First of all, the illusion of consciousness. Spinoza argues
that we are not the cause of our thoughts and actions, but
only assume that we are based on their affects upon us. This
leads to dualisms of substance (such as Descartes' mind/body
split). Deleuze insists on this point because he sees Spinoza
bypassing an important illusion of subjectivity: we suppose
that we are causes and not effects.
The illusion of consciousness, for Spinoza a result of
inadequate knowledge and sad affects, allows us to posit a
transcendental consciousness supposedly free from the
interventions of the world (as in Descartes). This is in fact
a blind-spot which precludes us from knowing ourselves as
caused, the practical meaning of which is that we deny our own
'sociality', as one mode amongst others, and the significance
of the relations that we enter into, which actually determine
our power to act, and our ability to experience active joy.
The second is the critique of morality. Spinoza's
Ethics, for Deleuze, constitutes a rejection of the
transcendent Good/Evil distinction in favour of a merely
functional opposition between good and bad. Good and Evil, for
Spinoza as for Lucretius and Nietzsche, are the illusions of a
moralistic world-view that does nothing but reduce our power
to act and encourages the experience of the sad passions (SPP
25; LS 275-8). The Ethics is for Deleuze rather an
incitement to consider encounters between bodies on the basis
of their relative 'goodness' for those modes that are
relating. The shark enters into a good relation with salt
water, which increases its power to act, but for fresh water
fish, or for a rose bush, salt water only degrades the
characteristic relations between the parts of the bush and
threatens to destroy its existence.
So actions have no transcendental scale to be measured upon
(the theological illusion), but only relative and perspectival
good and bad assessments, based on specific bodies. Thus the
Ethics is, for Deleuze, an 'ethology', that is, a guide
to obtaining the best relations possible for bodies.
Finally, Deleuze sees in Spinoza the rejection of the sad
passions. This point is linked to the last, and again closely
related to Nietzsche's critique of ressentiment and
slave morality. Sad passions are for Spinoza all those forces
which disparage life. For Deleuze, Spinoza,
denounces all the falsifications of life, all the values
in the name of which we disparage life. We do not live, we
only lead a semblance of life; we can only think of how to
keep from dying, and our whole life is a death worship.
(SPP 26)
The hinge that this practical reading of Spinoza turns on
is Deleuze's angle of approach to the Ethics. Rather
than emphasising the great theoretical structures found in the
first few sections, Deleuze emphasises the later part of the
book (particularly part V), which consists in arguments from
the point of view of individual modes. This approach puts the
importance on the reality of individuals rather than form, and
on the practical rather than the theoretical. In the preface
to the English translation of Expressionism in
Philosophy, he writes:
What interested me most in Spinoza wasn't his Substance,
but the composition of finite modes . . . That is: the hope of
making substance turn on finite modes, or at least of seeing
in substance a plane of immanence in which finite modes
operate . . ." (EPS 11)
Deleuze's reading of Spinoza has clear and profound
relations with all that he wrote after 1968, especially the
two volumes of Capitalism and Schizophrenia.
c. Nietzsche
Aside from Spinoza, Nietzsche is the most important
philosopher for Deleuze. His name, and central concepts that
he created appear almost without exception in all of Deleuze's
books. It would also be accurate to say that he reads both
Spinoza and Nietzsche together, one through the other, and
thus highlights the profound continuity of their thought.
The most significant work that Deleuze did with Nietzsche
was his highly influential study Nietzsche and
Philosophy, the first book in France to systematically
defend and explicate Nietzsche's work, still suspected of
fascism, after the second World War. This text was and is
extremely well regarded by other philosophers, including
Jacques Derrida (Derrida 2001), and Pierre Klossowski, who
wrote the other key French study on Nietzsche in the second
half of last century (Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle,
which is dedicated to Deleuze).
While Nietzsche and Philosophy does deal with
Nietzsche's polemical targets, its originality and strength
lies in its systematic exposition of the diagnostic elements
of his thought. Indeed, one critique of this text is that it
oversystematises a thinker and writer whose style of writing
overtly resists such a summary approach. For Deleuze, however,
it has been one of the hallmarks of bad readings of Nietzsche
that they have relied upon a non-philosophical reading, either
seeing him as a writer who attempts to assert other models of
thought over philosopher, or, more commonly, as an
obscurantist or (proto-) madman whose books have no coherence
or value.
Nietzsche, for Deleuze, develops a symptomatology based on
an analysis of forces that is elaborate, rigorous and
systematic. He argues that Nietzsche's ontology is monist, a
monism of force: "There is no quantity of reality, all reality
is already a quantity of force." (NP 40) This force, in turn,
is solely a force of affirmation, since it expresses only
itself and itself to its fullest; that is, force says 'yes' to
itself (NP 186). Deleuze's reading of Nietzsche starts from
this point, and accounts for the whole of Nietzsche's critical
typology of negation, sadness, reactive forces and
ressentiment on this basis. The polemical basis of Nietzsche's
work, for Deleuze, is directed at all that would separate
force from acting on its own basis, that is, from affirming
itself.
There is not one force, but many, the play and interaction
of which forms the basis of existence. Deleuze argues that the
many antagonistic metaphors in Nietzsche's writing should be
interpreted in light of his pluralist ontology, and not as
indications of some sort of psychological agressivity.
Nietzsche's ontology, then, retains the suppleness and
reliance on difference while remaining monist. Thus he, for
Deleuze, is characterised as an anti-transcendental thinker.
Deleuze's reading of Nietzsche demonstrates the extent to
which he rejected the traditional, or dogmatic image of
thought (see (4)(d) below), which relies upon a natural
harmony between thinker, truth and the activity of thought.
Thought does not naturally relate to truth at all, but is
rather a creative act (NP xiv), an act of affect, of force on
other forces: "As Nietzsche succeeded in making us understand,
thought is creation, not will to truth." (WP 54) There is no
room for seeing truth as abstract generality (NP 103) in
Deleuze's account of Nietzsche, but rather to see truth itself
as a part of regimes of force, as a matter of value, to be
assessed and judged, rather than as an innate disposition (NP
108).
Once again, in Nietzsche, we are confronted with the
problem of considering a philosopher who is generally
considered to be quite foreign to the tradition of empiricist
thought, as an empiricist. As with Spinoza, however, Deleuze's
reading of Nietzsche, as he himself indicates, relies upon his
characterisation of empiricist thought: as the rejection of
the transcendental, both in ontology and thought, and the
consequent affirmation of thought as creativity.
Deleuze's central empiricist
concepts
While Deleuze often refers to the central concepts of
empiricism as classically formulated by Hume in the
Treatise (association, habituation, convention etc.)
(ES; LS 305-7; DR 70-3; WP 201-2), he also develops,
throughout his work, a number of other key concepts which
should be considered as empiricist. The most prominent of
these are immanence, constructivism, and excess.
The key word throughout Deleuze's writings, as we have
seen, to be found in almost all of his main texts without
fail, is immanence. This term refers to a philosophy based
around the empirical real, the flux of existence which has no
transcendental level or inherent seperation. His last text,
published a few months before his death, bore the title,
"Immanence: a life . . ." (PI 25-33). Deleuze repeatedly
insists that philosophy can only be done well if it approaches
the immanent conditions of that which it is trying to think;
this is to say that all thought, in order to have any real
force, must not work by setting up trancendentals, but by
creating movement and consequences:
If you're talking about establishing new forms of
transcendence, new universals, restoring a reflective subject
as the bearer of rights, or setting up a communicative
intersubjectivity, then it's not much of a philosophical
advance. People want to produce 'consensus', but consensus is
an ideal that guides opinion, and has nothing to do with
philosophy. (N 152; cf. 145; WP chapter 2)
Deleuze's insistence on the concept of the immanent also
has an ontological sense, as we have seen in his studies of
Spinoza and Nietzsche, and which returns later in works such
as Difference and Repetition and Capitalism and
Schizophrenia: there is only one substance, and therefore
everything which exists must be considered on the same plane,
the same level, and analysed by way of their relations, rather
than by their essence.
Constructivism is the title that Deleuze uses to
characterise the movement of thought in philosophy. This has
two senses. Firstly, empiricism, immanent thought, must create
movement, create concepts if it is to be philosophy and not
just opinion or consensus. Deleuze and Guattari cite Nietzsche
on this point: "[Philosophers] must no longer accept concepts
as a gift, nor merely purify or polish them, but first make
and create them, present them and make them convincing." (WP
5)
Secondly, in relation to other philosophy, Deleuze
maintains that we do not just repeat what they have already
said (see (2) above): "Empiricism . . . [analyses] the states
of things, in such a way that non-pre-existent concepts can be
extracted from them." (D vii) This constructivism, for
Deleuze, holds weight in all areas of research, as he
demonstrates in his studies of literature, cinema and art (see
(6) below).
Constructivism, moreover, does not proceed along any
predetermined lines. There is nothing that is necessary to
create, for Deleuze: thought does not have a pre-given
orientation (see (4)(b) below). Empiricist thought is thus
always in some sense strategic (LS 17).
The concept of excess takes the place in Deleuze's thought
of the transcendent. Instead of an object, a table for
example, being determined and given its essence by a
transcendental concept or Idea (Plato) which is directly
applicable to it, or the application of a transcendental
category or schema (Kant), everything that exists is exceeded
by the forces which constitute it. The table does not have a
for-itself, but has existence within a field or territory,
which are beyond its meaning or control. Thus a table exists
in a kitchen, which is part of a three-bedroom family home,
which is part of a capitalist society. In addition, the table
is used to eat on, linking itself with the human body, and
another produced, consumable item, a hamburger. For Deleuze, one
can always analyse interminably in any direction these
relations of force, which always move beyond the horizon of
the object in question.
For
Deleuze, however, nothing is exceeded more than subjectivity.
This is not a statement of ontological priority, but bears on
the extreme privilege the conscious-to-self subject has had in
the history of Western thought, it is certainly here that
Deleuze makes his most significant use of the concept of
excess. Consider, for example: "Subjectivity is determined as
an effect." (ES 26). "There are no fewer things in the mind
that exceed our consciousness than there are things in the
body that exceed our knowledge." (SPP 18)
The point
is that human forces aren't on their own enough to establish a
dominant form in which man can install himself. Human forces
(having an understanding, a will, an imagination and so on)
have to combine with other forces: an overall form arises from
this combination, but everything depends on the nature of
other forces with which the human forces become linked. (N
117; cf. especially DR 254; 257-61)
While
Deleuze protests that he never made a big deal out of
rejecting traditional postulates like the subject (N 88), he
frequently writes about the notion of the exceeded subject,
from his first book on Hume and throughout his work. This in
some sense locates him in the landscape of what is known as
postmodern thought, along with other figures such as Jacques
Derrida, Jean-Francois Lyotard and Michel Foucault.
4. Difference And Repetition
Difference and Repetition (1968) is without doubt
Deleuze's most significant book in a traditional academic
style, and proposes the most central of his disruptions to the
canonical traditions of philosophy. However, precisely for
this reason, it is also one of his most difficult books,
dealing as it does with two age-old, overdetermined
philosophical topics, identity and time, and with the nature
of thought itself.
a. Difference-in-itself
Deleuze's main aim in Difference and Repetition is a
creative elaboration of these two concepts, but it essentially
precedes by way of a critique of Western philosophy. His
central thesis is,
That identity not be first, that it exist as a principle
but as a second principle, as a principle become; that it
revolve around the Different: such would be the nature of a
Copernican revolution which opens up the possibility of
difference having its own concept, rather than being
maintained under the domination of a concept in general
already understood as identical. (DR 41)
From Plato (DR 59-63) to Heidegger (DR 64-6), Deleuze
argues, difference has not been accepted on its own, but only
after being understood with reference to self-identical
objects, which makes difference a difference between. He
attempts in this book to reverse this situation, and to
understand difference-in-itself.
We can understand Deleuze's argument by way of reference to
his analysis of Plato's three-tiered system of idea, copy and
simulacrum (cf. LS 253-65). In order to define something such
as courage, we can have reference in the end only to the Idea
of Courage, an identical-to-itself, this idea containing
nothing else (DR 127). Courageous acts and people can be thus
judged by analogy with this Idea. There are also, however,
those who only imitate courageous acts, people who use courage
as a front for personal gain, for example. These acts are not
copies of the courageous ideal, but rather fakes, distortions
of the idea. They are not related to the Idea by way of
analogy, but by changing the idea itself, making it slip.
Plato frequently makes arguments based on this system, Deleuze
tells us, from the Statesman (God-shepherd,
King-shepherd, charlatan) to the Sophist (wisdom,
philosopher, sophist) (DR 60-1; 126-8).
The philosophical tradition, beginning with Plato (although
Deleuze detects some ambiguity here (eg. DR 59; TP 361)) and
Aristotle, has sided with the model and the copy, and
resolutely fought to exclude the simulacra from consideration,
either by rejecting it as an external error (Descartes (DR
148)), or by assimilating it into a higher form, via the
operation of a dialectic (Hegel (DR 263)).
While difference is subordinated to the model/copy scheme,
it can only be a consideration between elements, which gives
to difference a wholly negative determination, as a not-this.
However, Deleuze suggests, if we turn our attention to the
simulacra, the reign of the identical and of analogy is
destabilised. The simulacra exists in and of itself, without
grounding in or reference to a model: its existence is
"unmediated" (DR 29), it is itself unmediated difference. It
is for this reason that Deleuze makes his well-known claim
that a true philosophy of difference must be "inverted-" or
"anti-Platonism" (DR 127-8): the being of simulacra is the
being of difference itself; each simulacra is its own model.
We might well ask here: what provides the unity of the
different? How can we talk about the being of something that
is difference itself? Deleuze's answer is that precisely there
is no intrinsic ontological unity. He takes up here
Nietzsche's idea that being is becoming: there is an internal
self-differing within the different itself, the different
differs from itself in each case. Everything that exists only
becomes and never is.
Unity, Deleuze tells us, must be understood as a secondary
operation (DR 41) under which difference is pressed into
forms. The prominent philosophical notion he offers for such
unity is time (see (4)(c) below), but later, in
Anti-Oedipus, Deleuze and Guattari offer a political
ontology that shows how this process of becoming is fixed into
unitary formulations.
b. Contra-Hegel
Deleuze's arch-enemy in Difference and Repetition is
Hegel. While this critical stance is already clearly evident
in Nietzsche and Philosophy and from there throughout
his work, Deleuze's revaluation of difference itself takes as
its most essential form the rejection of the Hegelian
dialectic, which represents the most extreme development of
the logic of the identical.
The dialectic, Deleuze tells us, seems to operate with
extreme differences alone, even so far as acknowledging them
as the motor of history. Formed of two opposite terms, such as
being and non-being, the dialectic operates by synthesising
them into a new third term that preserves and overcomes the
earlier opposition. Deleuze argues that this is a dead end
which makes,
identity the sufficient condition for difference to
exist and be thought. It is only in relation to the identical,
as a function of the identical, that contradiction is the
greatest difference. The intoxication and giddiness are
feigned, the obscure is already clarified from the outset.
Nothing shows this more than the insipid monocentrality of the
circles in the Hegelian dialectic. (DR 263)
While offering a philosophical tool that sees difference at
the heart of being, the process of the dialectic removes this
affirmation as its most essential step.
The further consequence of this for Deleuze relates to the
place of negation in Hegel's system. The dialectic, in its
general movement, takes specific differences,
differences-in-themselves, and negates their individual being,
on the way to a "superior" unity. Deleuze argues in
Difference and Repetition that this step of Hegel's
mistakes ontology, history and ethics.
"Beneath the platitude of the negative lies the world of
'disparateness'" (DR 267). There is no resolution of the
differences-in-themselves into a higher unity that does not
fundamentally misunderstand difference. Here Deleuze is
clearly recalling his Spinozist and Nietzschean ontology of a
single substance that is expressed in a multiplicity of ways
(cf. DR 35-42; 269): In a famous sentence, he writes: "A
single voice raises the clamour of being." (DR 35)
Hegel is famous for asserting that the negating dialectic
is the motor of history, proceeding towards the
often-caricatured end of history and the realisation of
absolute spirit. For Deleuze, history does not have a
teleological element, a direction of realisation; this is only
an illusion of consciousness (cf. SPP 17-22):
History progresses not by negation and the negation of
negation, but by deciding problems and affirming differences.
It is no less bloody and cruel as a result. Only the shadows
of history live by negation . . . (DR 268)
Finally, regarding ethics, Deleuze argues that an ontology
based on the negative makes of ethical affirmation a
secondary, derived possibility: "The false genesis of
affirmation . . .: if the truth be told, none of this would
amount to much if it was not for the moral presuppositions and
practical implications of such a distortion." (DR 268)
c. Repetition and Time
For Deleuze, the central stake in the consideration of
repetition is time. As with difference, repetition has been
subjected to the law of the identical, but also to a prior
model of time: to repeat a sentence means, traditionally, to
say the same thing twice, at different moments. These
different moments must be themselves equal and unbiased, as if
time were a flat, featureless expanse. So repetition has
essentially been considered as the traditional idea of
difference over time understood in a common-sense way, as a
succession of moments. Deleuze asks if, given a renovated
understanding of difference as in-itself, we are able to
reconsider repetition also. But there is also an imperative
here, since, if we are to consider difference-in-itself over
time, based in the traditional logic of repetition, we once
again reach the point of identity. As such, Deleuze's critique
of identity must revaluate the question of time.
Deleuze's argument proceeds through three models of time,
and relates the concept of repetition to each of them.
The first is time as a circle. Circular time is mythical
and seasonal time, the repetition of the same after time has
passed through its cardinal points. These points may be simple
natural repetitions, like the sun rising daily, the movement
of summer to spring, or the elements of tragedy, which Deleuze
suggests operate cyclically. There is a sense of both destiny
and theology in the concept of time as a circle, as a
succession of instants which are governed by an external law.
When time is considered in this fashion, Deleuze argues (DR
70-9), repetition is solely concerned with habit. The subject
experiences the passing of moments cyclically (the sun will
come up every morning), and contracts habits which make sense
of time as a continually living present. Habit is thus the
passive synthesis of moments that creates a subject.
The second model of time is linked by Deleuze to Kant (KCP
vii-viii), and it constitutes one of the central ruptures that
the Kantian philosophy creates in thought, for Deleuze: this
is time as a straight line. In the Critique of Pure
Reason, Kant liberates time from the circular model by
proposing it as a form that is imposed upon sensory
experience. For Deleuze, this reverses the earlier situation
by placing events into time (as a line), rather than seeing
the chain of events constituting time by the passing of
present moments.
Habit can thus no longer have any power, since in this
model of time, nothing returns. In order for sense to be made
of what has occurred, there must be an active process of
synthesis, which makes of the past instances a meaning (DR
81). Deleuze calls this second synthesis memory. Unlike habit,
memory does not relate to a present, but to a past which has
never been present, since it synthesises from passing moments
a form in-itself of things which never existed before the
operation. The novels of Marcel Proust are for Deleuze the
most profound development of memory as the pure past, or in
Proust's terminology, as time regained. (DR 122; PS passim)
In this second model of time, repetition thus has an active
sense in line with the synthesis, since it repeats something,
in the memory, that did not exist before - this does not save
it, however, from being an operation of identity, nonetheless.
These two moments, the active constitution of a pure past, and
the disparate experience of a present yet to be synthesised
produces a further consequence for Deleuze: as in Kant, a
radical splitting of the subject into two elements, the I of
memory, which is only a process of synthesis, and a self of
experience, an ego which undergoes experience. (DR 85-7; KCP
viii-ix)
Deleuze insists that both of these models of time press
repetition into the service of the identical, and make it a
secondary process with regards to time. The final model of
time that Deleuze proposes attempts to make repetition itself
the form of time.
In order to do this, Deleuze relates the concepts of
difference and repetition to each other. If difference is the
essence of that which exists, constituting beings as
disparates, then neither of the first two models of time does
justice to them, insisting as they do on the possibility and
even necessity of synthesising differences into identities. It
is only when beings are repeated as something other that their
disparateness is revealed. Consequently, repetition cannot be
understood as a repetition of the same, and becomes liberated
from subjugation under the demands of traditional philosophy.
To give body to the conception of repetition as the pure
form of time, Deleuze turns to the Nietzschean concept of the
eternal return. This difficult concept is always given a
forceful and careful qualification by Deleuze whenever he
writes about it (eg. DR 6;41; 242; PI 88-9; NP 94-100): that
it must not be considered as the movement of a cycle, as the
return of the identical. As a form of time, the eternal return
is not the circle of habit, even on the cosmic level. This
would only allow the return of something that already existed,
of the same, and would result again in the suppression of
difference through an inadequate concept of repetition.
While habit returned the same in each instance, and memory
dealt with the creation of identity in order to allow
experience to be remembered, the eternal return is, for
Deleuze, only the repetition of that which
differs-from-itself, or, in Nietzsche's terminology, only the
repetition of those beings whose being is becoming: "The
subject of the eternal return is not the same but the
different, not the similar but the dissimilar, not the one but
the many . . ." (DR 126)
As such, Deleuze tells us, repetition as the third meaning
of time takes the form of the eternal return. Everything that
exists as a unity will not return, only that which
differs-from-itself. "Difference inhabits repetition." (DR
76). So, while habit was the time of the present, and memory
the being of the past, repetition as the eternal return is the
time of the future.
The superiority of this third understanding of repetition
as time has two main impetuses in Deleuze's argument. The
first is obviously that it keeps difference intact in its
movement of differing-from-itself. The second is as
significant, if for different reasons. If only what differs
returns, then the eternal return operates selectively (DR 126;
PI 88-9), and this selection is an affirmation of difference,
rather than an activity of representation and unification
based on the negative, as in Hegel.
d. The Image of Thought
Chapter three of Difference and Repetition provides
a novel approach to an important question in philosophy, the
problem of presuppositions. Deleuze pursues this topic again
later in A Thousand Plateaus (374-80), and when he
writes about conceptual personae in What is Philosophy?
(ch. 3); he had already written on images of thought in
Nietzsche and Philosophy (103-10) and Proust and
Signs (94-102).
An example is Descartes' celebrated phrase at the beginning
of the Discourse on the Method:
Good sense is the most evenly shared thing in the world
. . the capacity to judge correctly and to distinguish the
true from the false, which is properly what one calls common
sense or reason, is naturally equal in all men . .
For Descartes, thought has a natural orientation towards
truth, just as for Plato, the intellect is naturally drawn
towards reason and recollects the true nature of that which
exists. This, for Deleuze, is an image of thought.
Although images of thought take the common form of an
'Everybody knows . . .' (DR 130), they are not essentially
conscious. Rather, they operate on the level of the social and
the unconscious, and function, "all the more effectively in
silence." (DR 167)
Deleuze undertakes a thorough analysis of the traditional
philosophical image of thought, and lists eight features
which, in all aspects of philosophical pursuit, imply a
subordination of thought to externally imposed directives. He
includes the good nature of thought, the priority of the model
or recognition as the means of thought, the sovereignty of
representation over supposed elements in nature and thought,
and the subordination of culture to method (or learning to
knowledge). These all imply an a priori nature of thought, a
telos, a meaning and a logic of practice. These features,
crush thought under an image which is that of the Same
and the Similar in representation, but profoundly betrays what
it means to think and alienates the two powers of difference
and repetition, of philosophical commencement and
recommencement. (DR167)
It is this element, in Difference and Repetition,
that founds Deleuze's most serious criticism of the
traditional image of thought: that it fails to come to terms
with the true nature of difference and repetition. As a
result, it is fair to say that this moment of the book is
essential for understanding the way in which Deleuze both
wants to base his assessment of traditional philosophies of
identity and time, and how he wishes to exceed them: his
reformulation of difference and repetition is made possible by
this critique (cf. N 149).
The other critical angle Deleuze supplies here is related
to the first, and derives from Nietzsche's critique of Western
thought:
When Nietzsche questions the most general
presuppositions of philosophy, he says that these are
essentially moral, since Morality alone is capable of
convincing us that thought has a good nature and the thinker a
good will, and that only the good can ground the supposed
affinity between thought and the True. (DR132; cf. LS 3)
As we saw above regarding Hegel, the real point of concern
is that this image of thought is in the service of practical,
political and moral forces, it is not simply a matter of
philosophy, in segregation from the rest of the world.
To the question 'why do we have this image of thought?'
Deleuze, along with Nietzsche, that it is a moral image, and
is in the service of power, but there is also a more intrinsic
problem with thinking itself, that is only fully developed in
the Conclusion to What is Philosophy?, and this is that
thought itself is dangerous.
In contradistinction to the natural goodness of thought in
the traditional image, Deleuze argues for thought as an
encounter: "Something in the world forces us to think." (DR
139) These encounters confront us with the impotence of
thought itself (DR 147), and evoke the need of thought to
create in order to cope with the violence and force of these
encounters. The traditional image of thought has developed,
just as Nietzsche argues about the development of morality in
The Genealogy of Morals, as a reaction to the threat
that these encounters offer. We can consider the traditional
image of thought, then, precisely as a symptom of the
repression of this violence.
As a result, the relationship of philosophy to thought must
have two correlative aspects, Deleuze argues:
an attack on the traditional moral image of thought, but
also a movement towards understanding thought as
self-engendering, an act of creation, not just of what is
thought, but of thought itself, within thought (DR 147).
This is true, dangerous thought, but the sole thought
capable of approaching difference-in-itself and complex
repetition: thought without an image. .
The thought which is born in thought, the act of
thinking which is neither given by innateness nor presupposed
by reminiscence but engendered in its genitality, is a thought
without image. But what is such a thought, and how does it
operate in the world? (DR 167; cf. 132)
This final question directs us towards the central aim of
the two texts of Capitalism and Schizophrenia.
5. Capitalism And Schizophrenia - Deleuze And
Guattari
The collaborative texts of Deleuze and Felix Guattari,
particularly the two volumes of Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, are outside of the scope of the current
article (see the Deleuze and Guattari entry in this
encyclopaedia, forthcoming). However, two brief points are
important to note.
First, that despite the wide notoriety of these works as
obscurantist and non-philosophical, they bear a profound
relation to Deleuze's philosophical enterprise in general, and
develop in new ways many of his concerns: a commitment to an
immanent ontology, the importance of the social and the
political to the very heart of being, and the affirmation of
difference over the transcendental hierarchy in every aspect
of this work.
Secondly, the manner in which these texts are written by
the two writers, between the two and not seperately, means
that many new elements emerge that cannot be drawn from their
work individually. As such, regarding Deleuze, many of the
central ideas cited above do undergo an interesting and novel
transformation into a new direction: the very type of
relationship characterised in Capitalism and
Schizophrenia as a becoming.
6. Literature, Cinema, Painting
Deleuze's work on the arts, he never ceases to remind the
reader, are not to be understood as literary criticism, film
or art theory. Talking of the 1980's, during which he wrote
almost exclusively on the arts, he states the following:
let's suppose that there's a third period when I worked
on painting and cinema: images on the face of it. But I was
writing philosophy. (N 137)
This accords with the aims of Deleuze's empiricism (see (3)
above), to understand philosophy as an encounter (with a work,
philosophical or artistic, an object, a person) out of which
"non-pre-existent concepts," (DR vii) can be created.
Regarding his books on cinema, he is even more explicit:
Film criticism faces twin dangers: it shouldn't just
describe films but nor should it apply to them concepts taken
from outside film. The job of criticism is to form concepts
that aren't of course 'given' in films but nonetheless relate
specifically to cinema, and to some specific genre of film, to
some specific film or other. Concepts specific to cinema, but
which can only be formed philosophically. (N 58; C2 280)
All of Deleuze's work on artists can be assembled under the
rubric of the creation of new philosophical concepts that
relate specifically to the work at hand, yet which also link
these works with others more generally. Not a philosophy of
the arts per se, but a philosophical encounter with specific
artistic works and forms.
One feature that the artistic works also contain, distinct
from many of Deleuze's other books, is a concern with a
taxonomy of signs. In Proust and Signs, Francis
Bacon, and the Cinema books, Deleuze attempts to
develop a systematic approach of classifying different signs.
These signs are not linguistic (C1 ix), since they are not
themselves elements of a system, but rather are types of
emissions from a work. Proust, for example, on Deleuze's
account, understands experience itself as a reception of signs
by a proto-subject which must be understood properly, just as
the large variety of images discussed in Cinema 1 and
2 are categorised by Deleuze on the basis of C.S.
Pierce's semiotics.
Deleuze often comes to consider the questions 'what is the
nature of the artist, and of art?' Aside from his specific
elaborations of these questions in What is Philosophy?,
he is concerned to emphasise the radically active creative
nature of art and artists in his work in general. This
characterisation goes far beyond the general consideration of
artists as 'creative people', and highlights the manner in
which art is itself a creation of movement, not of
representations: that is, something radically new, an affect,
a movement of force or desire (cf. PS xi.,187 n1).
While the dominant Western tradition, from Plato to
Heidegger, places art in a relationship to truth, Deleuze
insists in every case on a Nietzschean argument (NP 102-3),
that the work of art only has relations with forces, and that
truth is a derivative, secondary formation: art is active.
In another register, Deleuze suggests that artists are
themselves created, within thought, and must be cultured and
afflicted by forces which exceed them to develop to the point
of creativity (NP 103-9; cf. (4)(d) above). These forces, in
turn, account for the frequent frailty of artists and
thinkers. While the work of art sets to work forces of life,
the artist themselves has experienced "too much", and this
wearies and sickens them (D 18; C2 189).
Deleuze's insistences that the artist is above all someone
who creates new ways of being and perceiving increases in
frequency and strength throughout the course of his texts on
art and artists.
a. Literature
Deleuze wrote extensively on literature throughout his
career. Aside from dedicating whole works to Proust (Proust
and Signs 1964), Leopold von Sacher-Masoch ("Coldness and
Cruelty"1969), and Kafka (Kafka: Towards a Minor
Literature 1975), and a large portion of The Logic of
Sense to Lewis Carroll, he also dealt in some detail with
a wide range of figures such as F. Scott Fizgerald, Herman
Melville, Samuel Beckett, Antonin Artaud, Heinrich von Kleist,
and Fyodor Dostoyevsky.
i. Marcel Proust
It is quite easy, if one wishes to attach a philosophical
point of view to Marcel Proust's work, to see it as a
phenomenology of memory and perception, in which his famous
text In Search of Lost Time would be oriented towards
an understanding of what underlies and gives substance to
experience and memory.
In essence, Deleuze proposes the opposite of the
phenomenological method. He reads Proust's work as an
anti-logos, that supposes, rather than a transcendental ego
which is the necessary feature of all experience, a passive,
receptive subject at the mercy of the signs and symptoms of
the world.
For what does in fact take place in In Search of Lost
Time, one and the same story with infinite variations? It
is clear that the narrator sees nothing, hears nothing . .
like a spider poised in its web, observing nothing, but
responding to the slightest sign . . . (AO 68)
Rather than memory, the central question of the
Search, being based within the subject, and as the
product of certain transcendental operations, it is a creation
of something which did not exist before by way of an original,
each-time unique, style of interpretation for experiences (PS
101). Deleuze uses the term 'anti-logos' on the grounds that
Proust, as he argues, refuses the representational model of
experience central to Western philosophy:
Everywhere Proust contrasts the world of signs and symptoms
with the world of attributes, the world of hieroglyphs and
ideograms with the world of analytic expression, phonetic
writing, and rational thought. What is constantly impugned are
the great themes inherited from the Greeks: philos, sophia,
dialogue, logos, phone. (PS 108)
In contrast, Deleuze characterises the Search as a
recasting of thought: thought is creative and not reminiscent
(Platonic and phenomenological).
ii. Leopold von
Sacher-masoch
Masoch features in a few of Deleuze's books (K 66-7; D
119-23), but most significantly in his long study "Coldness
and Cruelty". This early text is a critique of the unity of
the clinical and aesthetic notion "sado-masochism".
Deleuze argues here that this clinical concept fails to
account for the actual writings of the Maquis de Sade and
Sacher-masoch, along with making an unjustified unity from a
two quite distinct groups of symptoms.
Masoch is considered by Deleuze to be an important writer
of unusual power, and a master of suspense, the key literary
element of masochism. However, while de Sade has become
well-known, and his writings analysed, Deleuze suggests that
our poor understanding of Masoch's texts is one of the main
culprits in making the confused unity that is sadomasochism.
In fact, according to Deleuze, he offers us a new way of
understanding existence by displacing sexuality into the world
of power (M 12). Thus, Deleuze tells us, Masoch was in fact,
"a great anthropologist." (M 16)
Point by point, Deleuze develops a reading of the two
writers, Masoch in particular, that shows their profound
disparity. Alongside this is an analysis of the psychiatric
categories of sadism and masochism that reveals the same lack
of common ground.
Sadomasochism is one of these misbegotten names, a
semiological howler. We found in every case that what appeared
to be a common 'sign' linking the two perversions together
turned out on investigation to be in the nature of a mere
syndrome which could be further broken down into irreducibly
specific symptoms of the one or the other perversion. (M 134)
In "Coldness and Cruelty", Deleuze also elaborates a
critique of Freud that points in the direction of
Anti-Oedipus, although clearly more limited in scope.
iii. Franz
Kafka
Kafka: towards a minor literature can be
distinguished from Deleuze's other texts on literature in that
it was written with Guattari, and it strongly bears the stamp
of Anti-Oedipus, published just three years earlier,
and the concepts utilised there. In many ways, it can be read
as a development of the same themes in regard to Kafka's work.
This text is a marked departure from all of the dominant
interpretations of Kafka's writing, which is generally
considered either psychoanalytically (as a projection of
interior guilt onto the world through writing) or mythically,
that is, as a reserve of symbols and closely related to
negative theology and Jewish mysticism. Deleuze and Guattari
consider Kafka as a proponent of a joyful science, of writing
as a way of creating a line of flight or freedom from the
forms of domination. They write:
The three worst themes in many interpretations of Kafka
are the transcendence of the law, the interiority of guilt,
the subjectivity of enunciation. (K 45)
In contrast, Deleuze and Guattari read Kafka as a proponent
of the immanence of desire. The law is no more than a
secondary configuration that traps desire into certain
formations: bureaucracy, of course, is the main example in
Kafka's work, where offices, secretaries, lawyers and bankers
present figures of entrapment.
They also see Kafka as directly targeting the Oedipus
complex, the triangle of "daddy-mommy-me":
the too-well formed family triangle is really only a
conduit for investments of an entirely different sort that the
child endlessly discovers underneath his father, inside his
mother, in himself. The judges, commissioners, bureaucrats,
and so on, are not substitutes for the father; rather, it is
the father who is a condensation of all these forces that he
submits to and that he tries to get his son to submit to.
(K 11-2)
Thus, for Kafka, according to Deleuze and Guattari, the
family are a socially derived unit that works by trapping the
flow of desire. The interiority of guilt is replaced by the
exteriority of subjugation. This is best demonstrated in the
analysis of Kafka's famous short story, The
Metamorphosis (K 14-5).
They also wish to read Kafka, not as a writer of genius,
who expresses the superior insight of his inner sight, but as
a writer of minor literature. This is the key concept of
Deleuze and Guattari's reading of Kafka. Minor literature is a
writing that takes a dominant language (German, in Kafka's
case, French in Beckett's, and so forth), and pushes it until
it becomes a language of force, and not of signification (K
19). In turn, this connects immediately with the situation of
minorities, minority groups in the first instance, but also
the attempts that everyone makes to create a line of flight
outside of majoritarian or molar social formations.
As such, minor literature is an immediately political
writing (K 17), which connects the text immediately to
(micro-) political struggle. Thus the third substitution is
the collective, that is, political, nature of enunciation, for
the traditional model of the subjective intent behind the
author's words. Kafka, for Deleuze and Guattari, writes as a
node in a field of forces, rather than a Cartesian cogito,
sovereign in the castle of consciousness. "The superiority of
Anglo-american literature"
One clear feature of Deleuze's relationship to literature
is his outspoken appreciation for what he calls Anglo-American
literature, and its superiority over the literature of Europe.
What we find in great English and American novelists is
a gift, rare among the French, for intensities, flows,
machine-books, tool-books, schizo-books. (N 23)
The great European tradition in literature is analogous for
Deleuze to traditional philosophy: it always revolves around a
relationship to truth, the preservation of some kind of social
status quo, the sovereignty of the author over the text; as
Deleuze states, "everybody says "cogito" in the French novel."
The strength of Anglo-american literature for Deleuze is
rather that it rejects the idea of the book as a
representation of reality, and all of the adjacent problems
with the dogmatic image of literature, and presents the book
as a machine, as something which does things, rather than
signifying.
b. Cinema
Part of the reason for the impact of Deleuze's writings on
cinema is simply that he is the first important philosopher to
have devoted such detailed attention to it. Of course, many
philosophers have written about movies, but Deleuze offers an
analysis of the cinema itself as an artistic form, and
develops a number of connections between it and other
philosophical work.
Deleuze's first book is entitled Cinema 1: The
Movement-Image. It deals with cinema from its development
through to the second World War. For Deleuze, the cinema as an
art form is quite unique, and deals with its subject matter in
ways that no other form of art is capable of, particularly as
a way of relating to the experience of space and time.
Deleuze's analysis begins by coming to new understandings
of the concepts of the image and movement. The image, above
all, is not a representation of something, that is, a
linguistic sign. This definition relies upon the age-old
Platonic distinction between form and matter, in its modern
Saussurean form of signifier-signified. Rather, Deleuze wants
to collapse these two orders into one, and the image thus
becomes expressive and affective: not an image of a body, but
the body as image (C1 58).
This collapse comes about with reference to two
philosophers, Henri Bergson and Charles Sanders Pierce.
Deleuze dedicated a book-length study to the former entitled
Bergsonism (1968), and his use of his notions of
movement and time in the Cinema texts is already
presaged by this text. Movement for Bergson, Deleuze argues,
is not separable from the object which moves: they are
literally the same thing. Thus, no representative relationship
can be established without artificially halting the flow of
movement and thus misconstruing the frozen 'element' as
self-sufficient. There is only the flow of movement which
expresses itself in different ways. Among other things, this
is one of Deleuze's critiques of phenomenology (C1 56, 60).
Thus the early cinema is characterised for Deleuze by the
reign of what he calls the sensory-motor schema. This schema
is the unity of the viewed and the eye that views in dynamic
movement.
This model of the movement-image is precisely the nature of
cinema, for Deleuze. It does not falsify movement by
extracting segments and stringing them together in a
representative fashion, but creates a wide range of expressive
images. It is in order to come to terms with the varieties of
movement-images that Deleuze turns to Pierce, who developed,
"the most extraordinary classifications of images and signs .
. ." (C2 30). The main part of Cinema 1 is thus devoted
to using, with some alterations, Pierce's semiotic
classifications to describe the use of movement-images in
cinema, and their centrality before the second World War.
The movement from the first text to Cinema 2: The
Time-Image has a significance closely related to Kant's
so-called Copernican revolution in philosophy. Up until Kant,
time was subject to the events that took place within it, time
was a time of seasons and habitual repetition (see (3)(c)
above); it was not able to be considered on its own, but as a
measure of movement (C2 34-5; KCP iv.). One element of Kant's
achievement for Deleuze, as we have seen, is his reversal of
the time-movement relationship: he establishes time itself as
an element to which movement must be subordinated, a pure
time.
In the cinema, Deleuze argues, a similar reversal takes
place. The historico-cultural reason behind this reversal is
the event of World War two itself. With the great truths of
Western culture put so deeply in question by the before
unimaginable methods employed and their forthcoming results,
the sensory-motor apparatus of the movement-image are made to
tremble before the unbearable, the too-much of life's
possibilities, the potential of the present (C2 35). No longer
could the dogmatic truths that had guided society, and cinema
to an extent, allow the apparently 'natural' movement from one
thing to the next in an habitual fashion: 'natural' links
precisely lost their efficacy. And with the use of unnatural
or false links, which do not follow the sequence or narrative
affect of the movement-image, time itself, the time-image, is
manifested in cinema (Deleuze considers Orson Welles to be the
first auteur to make use of the time-image (C2 137)). Rather
than finding time as an, "indirect representation," (C2 35-6),
the viewer experiences the movement of time itself, which
images, scenes, plots and characters presuppose or manifest in
order to gain any sort of movement whatsoever.
Along with this 'external' reason, there is also for
Deleuze a motivation within cinema itself to go from the
movement-image to the time-image. The movement image has the
tendency, thanks to the habitual experience of movement as
normal and centered, to justify itself in relation to truth:
as Deleuze argues with regard to the dogmatic image of thought
(see (3)(d) above), there is the presupposition that thought
naturally moves towards truth. Of course, Deleuze suggests,
cinema, when truly creative, never relied upon this
presupposition, and yet, "the movement-image, in its very
essence, is answerable to the effect of truth which it invokes
while movement preserves its centres." (C2 142). In
questioning its own presuppositions, Deleuze argues, cinema
moved towards a new, different, way of understanding movement
itself, as subordinate to time.
This in turn leads Deleuze to abandon Pierce's semiotics to
a large degree, since it has no room for the time-image (C2
33-4ff.), and replaces him with Nietzsche. As we have seen in
our consideration of time in Difference and Repetition
(see (3)(c) above), Nietzsche is the philosopher who Deleuze
considers to have made the crucial move with regard to time,
surpassing even Kant.
One of the central consequences for cinema that this move
from movement-image to time-image makes again highlights one
of Deleuze's central concerns, to establish an ontology and a
semiology of force: "What remains? There remain bodies, which
are forces, nothing but forces." (C2 139) Since the cinema of
the time-image is concerned to liberate images from carrying
or implying time in order to form narrative (no less than
liberating time itself from narrative), images are themselves
free now to express forces, "shocks of force," (C2 139).
Scenes, movements and language become expressive rather than
representative.
c. Painting
Deleuze's central work in the visual arts is his monograph
Francis Bacon: logique de la sensation (the logic of
sensation), but he also engages with a large number of other
figures in various texts (eg. TP 492-500; WP ch.7), such as
Turner (AO 132), Van Gogh, Klee, Kandinsky and Cezanne.
Deleuze's book on Francis Bacon, as the title suggests, is
an attempt to construct a logic of sensations from the
artist's work (FB 7). This task is largely a taxonomic one.
Deleuze develops, throughout the book, a number of key
categorial notions and new concepts that allow him to move
away from the standard representational view of painting,
towards a painting of force, that presents force and creates
affects (sensations) rather than representing or describing a
scene. Three central ideas are at work.
The first is an elaboration of the concept of Figure. For
Deleuze, while the idea of figuration in painting has largely
been representational, he sees Bacon, and to some extent
Cezanne before him (FB 40, 76), collapsing the Figure into the
world of forces, placing it in a new relation to force. Thus
Bacon's cries, for which he is famous, place the figure in the
presence of force: ". . . painting will place the visible cry,
the mouth which cries, into a relation with force." (FB 41).
For Deleuze the cry expresses an extreme moment of life,
rather than suffering or horror. As with Kafka, Deleuze takes
Bacon's artistic work, is commonly considered very dark and
nihilistic, and considers it as a true sign of life, and of
struggle with death.
The second, a refrain familiar from all of his work,
relates to a notion of force that makes it ontologically and
artistically fundamental rather than politically oppressive,
much as desire is reconfigured in Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. It is in fact this move that allows
Deleuze's general 'positivism' towards Bacon, as we have just
seen: "Everything . . . is in relation with forces, everything
is force." (FB 40) In Francis Bacon, Deleuze thus
creates the notion of 'color-force', in order to understand
how color can be expressive of force rather than
representative (FB 94-7).
Finally, Deleuze draws on the difference between Western,
representational models of vision, and the haptic style of
Egyptian art, in which he sees a development of a mode of
writing/drawing which resists being hypostased into the
content/form duality common to philosophical understandings of
art.
7. What Is Philosophy?
We have already seen the significance of empiricism for
Deleuze's philosophy ((3) above). Throughout his work,
however, Deleuze gives a number of further formulations
concerning the aim and nature of philosophy. These can be
understood in two phases, an early critical naturalism and a
later vitalist constructivism.
Early reflections - Naturalism
In his early works in the history of philosophy,
culminating with The Logic of Sense, Deleuze expresses
an essentially critical model of philosophy. In his book on
Nietzsche, he writes:
When someone asks 'what's the use of philosophy?' the
reply must be aggressive, since the question tries to be
ironic and caustic. Philosophy does not serve the State or the
Church, who have other concerns. It serves no established
power. The use of philosophy is to sadden. A philosophy which
saddens no one, that annoys no one, is not a philosophy. It is
useful for harming stupidity, for turning stupidity into
something shameful. Its only use is the exposure of all forms
of baseness of thought. . . . Philosophy is at its most
positive as a critique, as an enterprise of demystification.
(NP 106)
It seems that this is the sole moment in Deleuze's
published work where he uses the term 'sadden' in a positive
manner, as something desirable, and this is an indication of
the strength by which he considers philosophy, in this early
sense, as an exercise in naturalism in the sense that
Lucretius uses this term, that is, as an attack on all forms
of mystification. Commenting on Lucretius, Deleuze makes the
following, extremely similar, remark:
The speculative object and the practical object of
philosophy as Naturalism, science and pleasure, coincide on
this point: it is always a matter of denouncing the illusion,
the false infinite, the infinity of religion and all of the
theologico-erotic-oneiric myths in which it is expressed. To
the question 'what is the use of philosophy?' the answer must
be: what other object would have an interest in holding forth
the image of a free man, and in denouncing all of the forces
which need myth and troubled spirit in order to establish
their power? (LS 278)
Deleuze's philosophical naturalism is thus critical,
Spinozist and Nietzschean: it sets as the aim of philosophy
the attack of all that belittles life: the sad passions of
Spinoza, the passive and reactive forces of Nietzsche, and
mythology, in Lucretian terms. Naturalism must not here be
understood as opposed to a cosmopolitanism, or constructivism,
Deleuze tells us. Rather, "Naturalism . . . directs its attack
against the prestige of the negative; it deprives the negative
of all of its power; it refuses the spirit of the negative the
right to speak in the name of philosophy." (LS 279)
Mythology, in the sense of these texts, is the eternal
danger for the operation of thought. Deleuze summarises this
immanent threat within thought (cf. (4)(d) above) as the
threat of stupidity:
Philosophy could have taken up the problem with its own
means and with the necessary modesty, by considering the fact
that stupidity is never that of others but the object of a
properly transcendental question: how is stupidity [...]
possible? (DR 151)
"What is Philosophy?" -
constructivism
From Difference and Repetition onwards, Deleuze,
while maintaining this critical aspect for philosophy,
develops a thorough-going constructivist view which manifests
itself in the final collaboration between Deleuze and
Guattari, What is Philosophy? This text involves
arguments about three central notions: the creation of
concepts, the presuppositions of philosophy, and the relations
between philosophy, science and art.
As we have seen, a certain doctrine of empiricist
constructivism runs through Deleuze's work from the beginning,
and on a number of levels. In What is Philosophy? this
becomes the central and explicit theme: "philosophy is the art
of forming, inventing, and fabricating concepts". (WP 2)
The philosopher's only business is concepts, Deleuze and
Guattari tell us, and the concept belongs only to philosophy
(WP 34). This is already clear when we consider Deleuze's
writings on the arts, which he considers to be philosophical
(see (6) above).
The fortunes of the concept, due to lack of attention by
philosophers, have fallen, to the point at which even
marketing has taken hold of it, in, "the general movement that
replaced Critique with sales promotion." (WP 10) However,
Deleuze and Guattari insist, philosophy still only has meaning
vis a vis the concept.
A concept is distinctly featured. It is a multiplicity, not
in itself a single thing, but an assemblage of components
which must retain coherence with the others for the concept to
remain itself (in this sense, it closely resembles the
Spinozist body). These components are singularities: "'a'
possible world, 'a' face, 'some' words . . ." (WP 20), and yet
become indiscernible when a part of a concept. Each concept
also has a relationship to other concepts by way of the
similar problems that they address, and by having similar
component elements, and Deleuze and Guattari describe their
relations by the use of the term vibration (WP 23).
Above all, however, the concept must not be confused with
the proposition, as in logic (WP 135 ff.), which is to say
that it is agrammatical. There is no necessary relation
between concepts, nor is there any given way of relating. The
logical functions of either/or, both/and and so forth, do not
do justice to the each-time created nature of conceptual
relations. Neither does the concept have a reference, in the
way that a proposition does. Rather, it is intensive and
expresses the virtual existence of an event in thought:
consider Descartes' famous cogito, which expresses the virtual
individual in relation to themselves and the world.
Finally, a concept has no relationship to truth, which is
an external determination, or presupposition, that places
thought at the service of the dogmatic image of thought: "The
concept is a form or a force" (WP 144). As such, concepts act,
they are affective, rather than significatory, or expressive
of the contents of ideas.
The question of presuppositions, already dealt with via the
concept of the image of thought (see (4)(d) above), is
examined in much greater depth by Deleuze and Guattari in
What is Philosophy? Indeed, their answer involves two
new concepts, the conceptual personae, and the plane of
immanence.
Conceptual personae (WP ch. 3) are the figures of thought
that give concepts their specific force, their raison
d'être. They are to be confused with neither psycho-social
types (WP 67), nor with the philosophers themselves (WP 64),
but are like concepts created. Deleuze and Guattari argue that
conceptual personae, while often only implicit in philosophy,
are decisive for understanding the significance of concepts.
To take again Descartes' cogito, the implicit conceptual
persona is the idiot, the regular person, uneducated,
untrained in philosophy, potentially betrayed by their senses
at every turn, and yet, able to have perfectly clear and
distinct knowledge of themselves, through the certainty of the
'I think, therefore I am'. Also mentioned are Nietzsche's
famous personae, both sympathetic and anti-pathetic:
Zarathustra, the last man, Dionysus, the Crucified, Socrates,
and so forth. (WP 64)
Conceptual personae are, for Deleuze and Guattari,
internal, non-philosophical preconditions for the practice of
creating concepts. These personae, in turn, are related to the
plane of immanence. This concept has clear and significant
resonances with other important elements of Deleuze's thought,
above all with his monist ontology of forces, and with his
practical emphasis on Nietzsche and Spinoza's ethics as
non-transcendental.
The plane of immanence (WP ch. 2) in thought is opposed to
the transcendent in traditional philosophy. Each time that a
transcendent is raised (Descartes' cogito, Plato's ideas,
Kant's categories), thought is arrested, and philosophy is
placed at the service of dominant ideas. For Deleuze and
Guattari, all of these instances of the transcendental stem
from the same problem: insisting that immanence be immanent to
"something". (WP 44-5)
For thought to exist, for concepts to be formed and then
given body through conceptual personae, they must operate
immanently, without the rule of a "Something" that organises
or stratifies the plane of immanence. Concepts exist on the
plane of immanence, and each philosopher, Deleuze and Guattari
tell us, must create such a plane.
The other main concern of What is Philosophy? is to
come to an understanding of the relations between philosophy,
art and science respectively. Deleuze and Guattari argue that
each discipline involves the activity of thought, and that in
each case it is a matter of creation. What differs is the
sphere of creation and the manner in which it is populated.
Art is concerned with the creation of percepts and affects
(WP 164), which are together sensation. Percepts are not
perceptions, in that they do not refer to a perceiver, and
neither are affects the feelings or affections of someone.
Just as we saw with concepts, affects and percepts are
independent beings which exist outside of the experience of a
thinker, and have no reference to a state of affairs. Deleuze
and Guattari write: "The work of art is a being of sensation
and nothing else: it exists in itself." (WP 164) The correlate
of the conceptual persona in art is the figure (which is
investigated in great depth in Deleuze's text on Bacon, see
(6)(c) above), and for the plane of immanence, art is created
on the plane of composition, which is likewise immanent only
to itself, and populated with the pure forces of percepts and
affects (WP 196).
The situation with science is similar. Science is the
activity of thought that creates functions. These functions,
in contrast to concepts, are propositional (WP 117), and form
the fragments from which science is able to piece together a
kind of makeshift language, one which however, does not have
any prior relation to truth, any more than philosophy does.
Functions have meaning in creating a referential point of
view, for Deleuze and Guattari, that is, in creating a basis
from which things can be measured. As such, the first great
functions are those such as absolute zero Kelvin, the speed of
light etc., in relation to which a plane of reference is
assumed. The plane of reference, again immanent to the
functions that populate it, gains consistency through the
strength and effectiveness of its functions. Also presupposed
by science, in What is Philosophy?, are partial
observers, the scientific counterpart of conceptual personae
and artistic figures.
The figure of the partial observer in science, as in
philosophy, is frequently implicit, and exists to give
direction to functions: we could consider Gallileo as an
example, whose functions regarding cosmology relate to a plane
of reference that gives a greater consistency to the functions
that the previous planes, which often relied upon a religious
transcendental structure that damaged and made scientific
thinking difficult by imposing a moral image of thought. The
partial observer in this case would be a figure that makes
certain functions in particular take shape and gain force
regarding a certain phenomena, such as the relation of the sun
to the moon: the heliocentrist.
8. Bibliography
a. Main texts
Below is a list of Deleuze's main works, in order of their
original publication in French. Francis Bacon: logique de
la sensation is currently the only major work without a
complete English translation, although one is currently being
completed, and should be expected shortly. Indicated in
parentheses after the original publication date are the
initials by which each text is referred to above. In addition
to the following, another resources seem particularly useful
to those not familiar with Deleuze: a long three-part
interview conducted with Claire Parnet, L'Abécédaire de
Gilles Deleuze. Parnet suggests a topic for each letter of
the alphabet, and Deleuze's answers, in most cases, are both
substantial and revealing. The video set is available to
purchase in French.
Empiricism and Subjectivity (1953 ES) trans.
Constanine Boundas (1991: Columbia University Press, New York)
Nietzsche and Philosophy (1962 NP) trans. Hugh
Tomlinson (1983: Althone Press, London)
Kant's Critical Philosophy (1963 KCP) trans. Hugh
Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam (1983: Althone Press, London)
Proust and Signs (1964 PS) trans. Richard Howard
(2000: University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
"Coldness and Cruelty" in Masochism (1967 M) trans.
Charles Stivale (1989: Zone Books, New York)
Bergsonism (1968 B) trans. Hugh Tomlinson and
Barbera Habberjam (1988: Zone Books, New York)
Difference and Repetition (1968 DR) trans. Paul
Patton (1994: Colombia University Press, New York)
Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (1968 EPS)
trans. Martin Joughin (1990: Zone Books, New York)
The Logic of Sense (1969 LS) trans. Mark Lester and
Charles Stivale (1990: Columbia University Press, New York)
Spinoza: Practical Philosophy (1970 SPP) trans.
Robert Hurley (1988: City Light Books, San Francisco)
(with Guattari) Anti-Oedipus - Capitalism and
Schizophrenia (1972 AO) trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem,
and Helen Lane (1977: Viking Press, New York)
(with Guattari) Kafka: Towards a Minor Literature
(1975 K) trans. Dana Polan (1986: University of Minnesota
Press, Minnesota)
(with Claire Parnet) Dialogues (1977 D) trans. Hugh
Tomlinson and Barbera Habberjam (1987: Althone Press, London)
(with Guattari) A Thousand Plateaus - Capitalism and
Schizophrenia (1980 TP) trans. Brian Massumi (1987:
University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
Francis Bacon: logique de la sensation (1981 FB:
Éditions de la différence, Paris)
Cinema: The Movement Image (1983 C1) trans. Hugh
Tomlinson and Barbera Habberjam (1989: University of Minnesota
Press, Minnesota)
The Time Image (1985 C2) trans. Hugh Tomlinson and
Robert Galeta (1989: University of Minnesota Press, Minnesota)
Foucault (1986 F) trans. Sean Hand (1988: University
of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque (1988 FLB) trans.
Tom Conley (1993: University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
Negotiations (1990 N) trans. Martin Joughin (1995:
Columbia University Press, New York)
(with Guattari) What is Philosophy? (1991 WP) trans.
Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell (1994: Columbia University
Press, New York)
Essays Critical and Clinical (1993) trans. Smith and
Greco (1997: University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis)
Pure Immanence: Essays on a life ed. John Rajchman
trans. Anne Boymen (2001 PI: Zone Books, New York)
b. Secondary texts
A good text that deals systematically with the whole body
of Deleuze's work, that is also quite easy to read, is the
Rajchman volume. Regarding Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, there are a number of commentaries
available; the Massumi text is perhaps the best known and most
consistent, although the general level of all secondary texts
in this area is very difficult. The Clamour of Being,
by Alain Baidou is a controversial interpretation of Deleuze's
work, particularly his ontology, from the perspective of
another important French philosopher who knew Deleuze. Michel
Foucault's 1977 article, "Theatricum Philosophicum," is also a
significant and well-known interpretation of Difference and
Repetition and The Logic of Sense.
Books and collections of essays
Ansell-Pearson ed., Deleuze and Philosophy: the
difference engineer (1997: Routledge, New York) - chapters
2-5, 6, 7 and 13 especially
Badiou, Alain Deleuze: the Clamour of Being trans.
Louise Burchill (2000: University of Minnesota Press,
Minneapolis)
Boundas and Olkowski eds., Gilles Deleuze and the
Theatre of Philosophy (1994: Routledge, New York)
Buchanan and Colebrook eds., Deleuze and Feminist
Theory (2000: Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh)
Hardt, Michael Gilles Deleuze: an apprenticeship in
philosophy (1993: University of Minnesota Press,
Minneapolis)
Lecercle, J. Philosophy through the Looking-Glass:
Language, Nonsense, Desire (1985: Hutchinson Press,
London)
Marks, John Gilles Deleuze: Vitalism and
Multiplicity (1998: Pluto Press, London)
Massumi, Brian A User's Guide to Capitalism and
Schizophrenia - deviations from Deleuze and Guattari
(1992: MIT Press, Cambridge)
Patton, Paul Deleuze and the Political (2000:
Routledge, New York)
Rajchman, John The Deleuze Connections (2000: MIT
Press, Cambridge)
Additional uncollected articles Braidotti, Rosi
"Embodiment, Sexual Difference, and the Nomadic Subject" in
Hypatia vol 8, no 1 pp 1-13 (Winter 1993)
Derrida, Jacques "I'm going to have to wander all alone" in
Brault and Nass eds., The Work of Mourning pp192-5
(2001: University of Chicago Press, Chicago)
Eribon, Didier "Sickness unto life - the life and works of
Gilles Deleuze" Artforum, v34 n7 (March 1996)
Foucault, Michel "Theatrum Philosophicum" in Language,
Counter-memory, Practice trans. Donald Bouchard and Sherry
Simon pp 165-198 (1977: Cornell University Press, Ithaca)
Goulimari, Pelagia "A minoritarian feminism? Things to do
with Deleuze and Guattari" Hypatia v14 i2 pp97-9
(Spring 1999)
Neil, David "The Uses of Anachronism: Deleuze's History of
the Subject" Philosophy Today 4: 42 Winter pp 418-31
(1998)
|