Fr. Seamus Mulholland
The Metaphysics of John Duns Scotus
The ecclesiastical condemnation of Aristoteleanism and
Arabian philosophy in 1277, which included some of the theses
of Thomas Aquinas, had a profound influence on the subsequent
development of medieval philosophy. Of course, opposition to
Greco-Arabian philosophy was nothing new in the 13th century.
Its opening decades had seen the newly translated work of
Aristotle and Averroes forbidden; yet their vogue spread, and
in the years that followed a reconciliation was attempted,
with varied success, between Christian dogma and the 'new
learning'. The 'heresy' of Latin Averroism as the end of the
century only confirmed the suspicion of the traditionalist
theologians that any Christian who accepted the credentials of
Aristoteleanism must arrive at conclusions contrary to faith.
The great condemnation of 1277 expressed their renewed
reaction to Aristotle and left an even deeper impression on
subsequent scholars of the inadequacy of philosophy and pure
human reason, in the name of theology. If, as had been
claimed, the 14th century is a period of criticism, it is
above all, a period of criticism, in the name of theology, of
philosophy and the pretensions of pure reason.
The attitude of Duns Scotus (1266-1308) of the
Franciscan Order, towards Aristotle and philosophy in general
is seen in his Object of Human Knowledge. According to
Aristotle, the human intellect is naturally turned towards
sensible things from the way is must draw all its knowledge by
way of sensation and abstraction. As a consequence, the proper
object of knowledge is the essence of a material thing. Now,
Duns Scotus was willing to agree that Aristotle correctly
described our present way of knowing, but he did contest that
he had said the last word on the subject and that he had
sufficiently explained what is in full right the object of our
knowledge. Ignorant of Revelation, Aristotle did not realise
that Man is now in a fallen state and that he was describing
the knowledge, not of an integral Man, but one whose mode of
knowing was radically altered by original sin.
Ignorance of this fact is understandable in Aristotle,
but it must have seemed inexcusable in a Christian theologian
like Thomas Aquinas. The Christian, Scotus argues, cannot take
Man's state as his natural one, nor, as a consequence, the
present servitude of his intellect to the senses and sensible
things as natural to him. We know from Revelation that Man is
destined to see God face-to-face. This would be impossible to
achieve is the material object of Man's knowledge was
restricted to the essences of material things, for God is not
contained within their scope. To be open to the vision of God,
the intellect must have an object broad enough to include Him,
and the only one that satisfies this condition is Being
(ousias). Being, therefore, in its full indetermination
to material and immaterial things is the first and adequate
object of the intellect.
When as a theologian Duns Scotus made this decision, he
was not only assuring the human intellect's capacity for the
beatific vision; he was also making metaphysics as a science
possible by marking out its proper object. Natural philosophy
moves in the realm of finite mobile being and theology in that
of infinite being. Metaphysics, on the other hand, has for its
object being as being, or the pure undetermined nature of
being. For Scotus this is not a logical universe. It is a
reality, and the most common of all. Taken simply in itself,
the notion of being abstracts from all the differences of
beings. That is why it is, for the metaphysician, univocal,
having one and the same meaning when applied to all things.
Only in its finite and infinite modes is being analogical.
Being has, consequently, a univocity in Duns Scotus
which is not found in Thomas Aquinas. For Thomas did not treat
of being as if it were a nature or essence; rather it was for
him that which is, at whose centre is an act of
existing. And since every act of existing is irreducible to
every other, there is a radical otherness in every
being which the work of abstraction can never erase. That is
why in the philosophy of Thomas Aquinas being is, for the
metaphysician, not a univocal, but an analogical, concept.
It was the Arabian philosopher, Avicenna, who taught
Scotus to conceive of every essence in an absolute state,
natura tantum, and at the same time suggested to him
his solution of the classic problem of universals. The Scotist
nature, like the Avicennian, is simply what the definition of
it signifies. Now, neither individuality nor universality is
included within thje definition of any nature. When, for
example, I define 'humanity' I mention its essential parts,
'animality' and 'rationality', but I do not see whether it is
individual or universal. Indeed, in itself, it is entirely
indifferent to being one or the other or both at the same
time. It can be individual in real existence and universal in
mind and still remain basically the same nature, for these
modalities are entirely accidental to it. Suppose that the
nature were of itself universal. Then it could never be
individual; but as a matter of fact it is individual in the
world of existing things. On the other hand, if it were by its
very nature individual, it could never be universal, but it is
universal in the mind. Consequently, the nature in itself must
be absolute, abstracting from both individuality and
universality.
In the metaphysical architecture of Duns Scotus
absolute nature does not exist as such. Humanity, for
instance, does not exist except in individual men and women
and in the concept which we form of it. But it is not on that
account simply a conceptual entity. Socuts says that it is a
real being. This real being is contracted or limited by an
'individual difference' or 'haecceity', commonly known in
Scotists studies as 'thisness' which renders the nature
individual. Following upon this contraction of the essence or
the nature, the individual is actualised by existence, which,
at least in creatures, is the ultimate act of a thing, related
to it simply as a mode of being.
If this is true, it is then evident that essence plays
the central and primary role in the metaphysics of Duns
Scotus. The metaphysical nucleus, so to speak, of an
individual thing is an essence which is limited by different
modalities which are purely accidental to it. That is why the
metaphysical universe of Duns Scotus has been called
'essentialist,' in distinction to the 'existentialist'
metaphysics of Thomas Aquinas (in calling the metaphysics of
Thomas Aquinas 'existentialist' there is no intention of using
the word as it is applied to the thought of such moderns as
Satre or Marcel. It is used simply to express the primordial
importance of the act of existing in that metaphysics), in
which the metaphysical centre of an individual thins is an act
of existing and its essence is but a limitation of that act.
Because they do not agree in their notions of being, the
metaphysics of Duns Scotus and Thomas Aquinas are
fundamentally different. To confuse them and to equate Scotism
with Thomism is simply to invite a gross misunderstanding of
both doctrines.
On the other hand, seen in its own light, the
architecture of the metaphysical universe of Duns Scotus is
entirely intelligible. He carefully distinguishes between two
orders of real beings: the order of beings (res) and the order
of formalities or realities (realitates, formalitates)
which are in things. Things are such that one can exist in
separation from the other, if not naturally (like Peter and
Paul), at least by the omnipotence of God (as matter can exist
apart from form). Realities or formalities, however, cannot
possibly exist separately. They are only formally
non-identical, in the sense that one is not contained within
the formal definition of the other. In Peter, for example,
rationality is not contained within the definition of
animality and his individuality as Peter is not contained
within the definition of his humanity; otherwise there could
be no animality which is not rational and no humanity other
than Peter's.
What is markedly characteristic of the metaphysics of
Duns Scotus is that he attributed reality even to these
formalities. They are not simply abstractions of the mind
(Aquinas); they abstract from each other even before the mind
considers them. Each has a real being of its own and a real
unity distinct from that of individual things. Peter and Paul,
for instance, are each numerically one. But in them there is
present humanity, animality, substance etc., each of which is
formally non-identical with the others and constitutes a real
being with its own specific or generic unity. True, Duns
Scotus always maintained that individual things are most
worthy of being called 'real', and that their numerical unity
is a 'major unity'. Still, formalities are also real, and
their generic or specific unity is for a him a real 'minor
unity', and not simply a unity in the conceptual order.
Scotus conceived of an individual thing, then, as a
coming together of of many formalities or natures of this
sort. All of which are made individual or concretised by an
'individual difference' or 'haecceity'. But even though these
formalities are individualised in things, in their own order
they remain common of universal. That is why Scotus can say,
paradoxically, that only individual things exist, but that
there is something common in reality which is not of
itself individual. This means simply that in the order of
existing things there are only individuals: there are no
existing universal things. But in the order of
formalities or essences there are common natures which guard
their commonness within their own order even when they are
individual in the order of things.
The reason why Scotus says that there are common
natures in reality is to assure a suitable object for
knowledge. The primary object of knowledge and science is not
individual things but universals. Now, there are two kinds of
science: one which concerns conceptual entities, namely,
Logic, and another, such as physics and metaphysics, which
concerns real Being. Since the object of both kinds of science
is universal, there must, then, be two kinds of universals:
the complete universal, which is the product of the intellect
and the object of logic, and the incomplete universal or
common nature which is the object of the science of real being
-metaphysics.
The metaphysical universe of Duns Scotus, therefore, is
people not only with individual things but also with real
common natures which the intellect has merely to eek out to
read their intelligible messages. In such a world even the
sense perceive a reality which is in a way universal.
According to Duns Scotus, the object of sensation is not
properly an individual thing as individual, but a reality
common to all sensible objects of one genus, the greenness,
for example, of all green things. Under these circumstances
there is no need of an abstractive process of the intellect,
in the way which Thomas Aquinas proposes, by which the
intelligible object, bearing the stamp of singularity in a
sensible image, must be rendered universal and actually
intelligible in order to be known. For the object present to
our cognitive faculties is a common nature in which, the Agent
Intellect can read, as an open book, the intelligible object
from which the concept will be born.
By his insistent realism of common natures, Duns Scotus
placed himself in the long line of medieval Christian
Platonists, all of whom agree in some way that there is a
universality or community outside the mind corresponding to
our universal concepts. But, of course, historical Platonism
is realised in very different forms. The rather crude realist
philosophies of Boethius and John Scotus Eriugena (often
confused with Duns Scotus) and William of Champeaux are a far
cry from the refined realism of Duns Scotus; but the same
Platonic inspiration between them can be seen behind them all.
And just as medieval Platonism aroused the unrelenting
criticism of Peter Abelard, so the Platonism of the 14th
century found an even more formidable opponent in William of
Ockham.
|