Divine Immanence
{im' - uh - nens}
Advanced Information
In philosophy and theology, divine immanence refers to the omnipresence of
God in the universe. The theory in its extreme form is Pantheism, in which God
and the world are virtually identical. Proponents of Monotheism, however,
have tempered the concept of immanence by positing the parallel doctrine of
divine Transcendence. Thus, in Judaism and Christianity, God is considered
omnipresent and active in human affairs as creator, sustainer, judge, and
redeemer, but is also considered elevated above and distinguished from the
universe.
Immanence
Advanced Information
Immanence is a conception in philosophy and theology that the intelligent and
creative force or being that governs the universe pervades the natural world.
Immanence is a fundamental doctrine of pantheism and can be contrasted with
transcendence, which conceives of the intelligent and creative force as existing
outside the natural world. In pantheistic systems of thought, for example,
all material objects in the universe are pervaded with the infinite divine
presence.
In Judeo-Christian religions, however, God both participates in the universe,
that is, is present and active in the natural world; and at the same time,
transcends, that is, figuratively, rises above, the universe he created.
Immanence
Advanced Catholic Information
(Lat. in manere, to remain in)
Immanence is the quality of any action which begins and ends within the
agent. Thus, vital action, as well in the physiological as in the intellectual
and moral order, is called immanent, because it proceeds from that spontaneity
which is essential to the living subject and has for its term the unfolding of
the subject's constituent energies. It is initiated and is consummated in the
interior of the same being, which may be considered as a closed system. But is
this system so shut in as to be self-sufficient and incapable of receiving
anything from without? -- or can it enrich itself by taking up elements which
its environment offers and which are at times even necessary, as nourishment is
to the immanent activity of the body? This is the problem which the philosophies
of immanence propose and attempt to solve, not only in respect to man considered
as a particular being, but also in respect to the universe considered as a
whole. It is, indeed, with reference to this latter aspect that the controversy
arose in ancient times.
HISTORICAL SKETCH
The doctrine of immanence came into existence
simultaneously with philosophical speculation. This was inevitable, since man
first conceived all things after his own likeness. He regarded the universe,
then, as a living thing, endowed with immanent activity, and working for the
full unfolding of its being. Under the veil of poetic fictions, we find this
view among the Hindus, and again among the sages of Greece. The latter hold a
somewhat confused Hylozoism: as they see it, the cosmos results from the
evolution of a single principle (water, air, fire, unity), which develops like
an animal organism. But Socrates, coming back to the study "of things human",
refuses to look upon himself as merely part and parcel of the Great All. He
asserts his independence and declares himself distinct from the universe; and
thus he shifts the pivotal problem of philosophy. What he professes is, indeed,
the immanence of the subject, but that immanence he does not conceive as
absolute, for he recognizes the fact that man is subject to external influences.
Thenceforward, these two conceptions of immanence are to alternate in ascendancy
and decline. After Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, absolute immanence regains
its sway through Zeno of Cittium, who gives it its clearest expression. In turn
it falls back before the preaching of Christianity, which sets forth clearly the
personality of man and the distinction between God and the world. The
Alexandrians, in the wake of Philo, impart a new lustre to the doctrine of
absolute immanence; but St. Augustine, borrowing from Plotinus the Stoic notion
of "seminal principles", contends for relative immanence which in the Middle
Ages triumphs with St. Thomas. With the Renaissance comes a renewal of life for
the theory of absolute immanence. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries,
on the contrary, Descartes and Kant maintain the transcendency of God, though
recognizing the relative immanence of man. But their disciples exaggerate this
latter fact and thus fall into subjective monism: the ego is shut up in its
absolute immanence; it posits the non-ego. After Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel,
the same path is taken by Cousin, Vacherot, Bergson, and many others. The
principle of absolute immanence becomes a dogma which they seek to impose upon
contemporary philosophy. It confronts revealed religion, and appears as one of
the sources of modernism, which it thus brings into close proximity with liberal
Protestantism. The notion of immanence is at the present day one of the centres
around which the battle is being fought between the Catholic religion and
monism.
Before passing on to larger development, we note that;
- (1) under its various aspects, the conception of immanence is the
interpretation and extension of a fact observed in the living subject;
- (2) in every age it takes on two parallel and opposite forms, which the
Encyclical "Pascendi gregis" defines in an eminently philosophical way, as
follows: "Etenim hoc quærimus; an ejusmodi 'immanentia' Deum ab homine
distinguat necne? Si distinguit, quid tum a catholica doctrina differt aut
doctrinam de revelatione cur rejicit? Si non distinguit, pantheismum habemus.
Atqui immanentia haec modernistarum vult atque admittit omne conscientiæ
phenomenon ab homine, ut homo est, proficisci" (For, we ask, does this
"immanence" make God and man distinct or not? If it does, then in what does it
differ from the Catholic doctrine? or why does it reject what is taught in
regard to revelation? If it does not make God and man distinct, it is
Pantheism. But this immanence of the Modernists would claim that every
phenomenon of consciousness proceeds from man as man).
DIVISION
From this general consideration of the subject the following
division arises.
A. The doctrine of immanence,
- (1) absolute,
- (2) relative.
And, as this doctrine has of late years given birth to a new method in
apologetics, we shall next consider:
B. The employment of the method of immanence,
- (1) absolute,
- (2) relative.
A. The Doctrine of Immanence
(1) Absolute Immanence
(a) Its Historical Evolution
At its outset the doctrine of immanence,
properly so called, was concerned with solving the problem of the world's origin
and organization: the universe was the resultant of an absolutely necessary,
immanent evolution of one only principle. The Stoics, who gave it its first
exact formula, virtually revived the pre-Socratic cosmogonies. But they shut up
in matter first the "Demiurgic Word", in which Plato saw the efficient cause of
the cosmos; and, then, the transcendently lovable and desirable "Supreme
Intelligence", postulated by Aristotle as the final cause of universal activity.
There existed, then, but one principle under a seeming duality; it was
corporeal, though it expressed itself sometimes in terms of passivity, when it
was called matter, and sometimes in terms of activity, when it was called
force, or cause. It was the technic fire presiding over the
genesis of the world; it was the Divine seminal principle from which all things
were born (pyr technikon, Logos spermatikos). This principle, which is
the first to move, is also the first to be moved, since nothing is outside of
it; all beings find in it their origin and their end, they are but successive
moments in its evolution, they are born and they die through its perpetual
becoming. The fiery spirit seems to move the chaotic mass as the soul moves the
body, and this is why it is called the "soul of the world". Human souls are but
sparks from it, or rather its phenomena, which vanish at death and are
re-absorbed into the bosom of nature. This is Hylozoism carried to its ultimate
expression.
The Greek and Roman Stoics changed nothing in this conception. Philo alone,
before Christianity, attempted to transform it. Pursuing the syncretic method
which he brought into repute in the School of Alexandria, he undertook to
harmonize Moses, Plato, and Zeno. Thus he was led into a sort of inverted
Stoicism, setting up at the origin of all things no longer a corporeal seminal
principle, but a spiritual God, perfect, anterior to matter, from whom
everything is derived by a process of outflow and downflow continued without
limit. Proclus, Porphyry, Jamblicus, and Plotinus adopted this emanationist
Pantheism, which formed the basis of their neo-Platonism. From Egypt the
Alexandrian ideas spread over the West through two channels. First, in the
fourth century, they entered Spain with a certain Mark, who had lived at
Memphis; in Spain they developed by amalgamating with Manichæism under the
influence of Priscillian, and after the German conquest of Spain they passed
into Gaul. In the latter country, moreover, they were propagated by the Latin
translations of Boethius. Later on, we find traces of them in Scotus Eriugena
(ninth century), then in Abelard (twelfth century), Amaury of Bêne, and David of
Dinant (twelfth and thirteenth centuries), and especially in the celebrated
Meister Eckhart (fourteenth century). Soon after this the Renaissance restores
the ancient doctrines to honourable consideration, and the philosophy of
immanence reappears in the commentaries of Pomponatius on Aristotle and those of
Marsilio Ficino on Plotinus. Giordano Bruno saw in God the monad of monads, who
by an inward necessity produces a material creation which is inseparable from
Himself. Vanini made God immanent in the forces of nature, while, according to
Jacob Böhme, God acquires reality only through the evolution of the world. By an
unbroken tradition, then, the doctrine of immanence comes down to modern times.
The Cartesian revolution seems even to favour its development. Exaggerating the
distinction between soul and body, the former of which moves the latter by means
of the pineal gland, the mechanical theories prepared the way for Malebranche's
occasionalism: God alone acts; "there is but one true cause, because there is
but one true God." Spinoza, too, admits only one cause. A disciple of Descartes
in the geometrical rigour of his deductive processes, but still more a disciple
of the rabbis and of Giordano Bruno in the spirit of his system, he sets up his
natura naturans unfolding its attributes by an immanent progression. This
is all but the revival of Alexandrian thought.
True Cartesianism, however, was not favourable to theories of this sort, for
it is based on personal evidence, and it distinguishes sharply between the world
and its transcendent cause. With its vivid realization of the importance and
independence of the individual, it follows, rather, the Socratic tradition. That
insight, defined and purified by Christianity, had all along served as a barrier
against the encroachment of the doctrine of absolute immanence. It could not but
derive fresh strength from the philosophy of Cogito, ergo sum, and
it was indeed strengthened even to excess. Jealous of its own immanence, which
it had learned to know better than ever, the human mind overshot its first
intention and turned the doctrine of absolute immanence to its own profit. At
first it sought only to solve the problem of knowledge, while keeping entirely
clear of empiricism. In the Kantian epoch it still claimed for itself only a
relative immanence, for it believed in the existence of a transcendent Creator
and admitted the existence of noumena, unknowable, to be sure, but with which we
maintain relations. Soon the temptation becomes stronger; having hitherto
pretended to impose its own laws on knowable reality, thought now credits itself
with the power of creating that reality. For Fichte, in fact, the ego not only
posits knowledge, it also posits the non-ego. It is the pre-eminent form of the
Absolute (Schelling). No longer is it the Substance that, as natura
naturans, produces the world by a process of derivation and degradation
without limit; it is an obscure germ, which in its ceaseless becoming, rises to
the point of becoming man, and at that point becomes conscious of itself. The
absolute becomes Hegel's "idea", Schopenhauer's "will", Hartmann's
"unconscious", Renan's "time joined to the onward tendency" (le Temps joint à
la tendance au progrès), Taine's "eternal axiom", Nietzsche's "superman",
Bergson's "conscience". Under all the forms of evolutionistic monism, lies the
doctrine of absolute immanence.
Considering the religious tendencies of our age, it was inevitable that this
doctrine should have its corresponding effect in theology. The monism which it
preaches, setting aside the idea of separateness between God and the world, also
removes entirely the distinction between the natural order and the supernatural.
It denies anything transcendent in the supernatural, which, according to this
theory, is only a conception springing from an irresistible need of the soul, or
"the ceaseless palpitation of the soul panting for the infinite" (Buisson). The
supernatural is but the product of our interior evolution; it is of immanent
origin, for "it is in the heart of mankind that the Divine resides". "I am a
man, and nothing Divine is foreign to me" (Buisson). Such is the origin of
religion in this view. And herein we recognize the thesis of liberal
Protestantism as well as that of the Modernists.
(b) The actual content of the doctrine of Absolute Immanence
As it is
nowadays presented, the doctrine of absolute immanence is the resultant of the
two great currents of contemporary thought. Kant, reducing everything to the
individual consciousness, and declaring all metaphysical investigation to be
illusory, locks the human soul in its own immanence and condemns it thenceforth
to agnosticism in regard to transcendent realities. The Positivist movement
reaches the same terminus. Through mistrust of that reason which Kant had
exalted to such a degree, Comte rejects as worthless every conclusion that goes
beyond the range of experience. Thus the two systems, setting out from opposite
exaggerations, arrive at one and the same theory of the unknowable: nothing is
left us now but to fall back upon ourselves and contemplate the phenomena which
emerge from the depths of our own ego. We have no other means of information,
and it is from this inner source that all knowledge, all faith, and all rules of
conduct flow out by the immanent evolution of our life, or rather of the Divine
which thus manifests itself through us. This initial position determines the
solutions which the doctrine of immanence furnishes for the problems concerning
God and Man.
(i) God
The problems of the Divine life and action are among the
foremost to interest the partisans of absolute immanence. They talk incessantly
of Trinity, Incarnation, and Redemption, but only, as they claim, to do away
with the mysteries and to see in these theological terms merely the symbols that
express the evolution of the first principle. Philo's Trinity, like that of
neo-Platonism, was an attempt to describe this evolution, and the moderns have
only resuscitated the Alexandrian allegory. The great being, the great fetish,
and the great medium (Comte), the evolving idea, the evolved idea, and their
relation (Hegel), unity, variety and their relation (Cousin) -- all these, in
the thought of their originators, are but so many revivals of the Oriental
myths. But conscience now demands the abolition of all such symbols. "The
religious soul is in fact forever interpreting and transforming the traditional
dogmas" (Sabatier), because the progress of the absolute reveals to us new
meanings as it makes us more fully conscious of the Divinity that is immanent in
us. Through this progress the incarnation of God in humanity goes on without
ceasing, and the Christian mystery (they make the blasphemous assertion) has no
other meaning. There can be no further question of a redemption; nor could there
have been an original fall, since in this view, disobedient Adam would have been
God Himself. At most the pessimists admit that the Supreme will, or the
unconscious, which blundered into the production of the world, will recognize
its blunder as it rises to consciousness in individuals, and will repair that
blunder by annihilating the universe. In that hour of cosmic suicide, according
to Hartmann, the Great Crucified will have come down from his cross. Thus is
Christian terminology incessantly subjected to new interpretations. "We still
speak of the Trinity . . . , of the Divinity of Christ, but with a meaning more
or less different from that of our forefathers". Buisson, in his "La Religion,
la Morale et la Science", thus explains the influence of the doctrine of
immanence upon the interpretation of dogmas in liberal Protestantism.
(ii) The World, Life, and the Soul
To explain the origin of the world,
the evolution of the Divine principle is put forward. This hypothesis would also
account for the organization of the cosmos. Hence the universal order is
considered as the outcome of the action of blind energies, and no longer as the
realization of a plan conceived and executed by a providence. From the
physico-chemical forces life issues; the absolute slumbers in the plant, begins
to dream in the animal, and at last awakens to full consciousness in man.
Between the stages of this progress there is no breach of continuity; it is one
and the same principle which clothes itself in more and more perfect forms, yet
never withdraws from any of them. Evolutionism and transformism, therefore, are
but parts of that vast system of absolute immanence in which all beings enfold
one another, and none is distinct from the universal substance. Consequently,
there is no longer any abyss between matter and the human soul; the alleged
spirituality of the soul is a fable, its personality an illusion, its individual
immortality an error.
(iii) Dogma and Moral
When the Absolute reaches its highest form in the
human soul, it acquires self-consciousness. This means that the soul discovers
the action of the Divine principle, which is immanent in it as constituting its
essential nature. But the perception of this relation with the Divine -- or,
rather, of this "withinness" of the Divine -- is what we are to call Revelation
itself (Loisy). At first confused, perceptible only as a vague religious
feeling, it develops by means of religious experience (James), it becomes
clearer through reflexion, and asserts itself in the conceptions of the
religious consciousness. These conceptions formulate dogmas -- "admirable
creations of human thought" (Buisson) -- or rather of the Divine principle
immanent in human thought. But the expression of dogmas is always inadequate,
for it marks but one moment in the religious development; it is a vesture which
the progress of Christian faith and especially of Christian life will soon cast
off. In a word all religion wells up from the depths of the sub-conscious
(Myers, Prince) by vital immanence; hence the "religious immanence" and the more
or less agnostic "symbolism" with which the Encyclical "Pascendi gregis"
reproaches the Modernists.
The human soul, creator of dogmas, is also the creator of moral precepts, and
that by an absolutely autonomous act. Its will is the living and sovereign law,
for in it is definitively expressed the will of the God immanent in us. The
Divine flame, which warms the atmosphere of our life, will enevitably cause
those hidden germs of morality to develop which the absolute has implanted.
Hence, there can be no longer any question of effort, of virtue, or of
responsibility; these words have lost their meaning, since there is neither
original sin nor actual and freely willed transgression. There is no longer any
blameworthy concupiscence; all our instincts are impregnated with Divinity, all
our desires are just, good, and holy. To follow the impulse of passion, to
rehabilitate the flesh (Saint-Simon, Leroux, Fourrier), which is one form under
which the Divinity manifests itself (Heine), this is duty. In this way, indeed,
we cooperate in the redemption which is being accomplished day by day, and which
will be consummated when the absolute shall have completed its incarnation in
humanity. The part which moral science has to play consists in discovering the
laws which govern this evolution, so that man in his conduct may conform to them
(Berthelot) and thus ensure the collective happiness of humanity; social utility
is to be hence-forward the principle of all morality; solidarity (Bourgeois),
which procures it, is the most scientific form of immanent morality, and of this
man is, in the universe, the beginning and the end.
(2) Relative Immanence
(a) Its Historical Evolution
Since the day when Socrates, abandoning the
useless cosmogonic hypotheses of his predecessors, brought philosophy back to
the study of the human soul, whose limits and whose independence he defined --
since that time the doctrine of relative immanence has held its ground in
conflict with the doctrine of absolute immanence. Relative immanence recognizes
the existence of a transcendant God, but it also recognizes, and with remarkable
precision, the immanence of Psychical life. It is upon the evidence of this
fact, indeed, that the admirable pedagogical method, known as maieutic,
is founded. Socrates thoroughly understood that knowledge does not enter our
minds ready made from without; that it is a vital function, and therefore
immanent. He understood that a cognition is not really ours until we have
accepted it, lived it, and in some sort made it over for ourselves. This
certainly attributes to the life of thought a real immanence, not, however, an
absolute immanence; for the soul of the disciple remains open to the master's
influence.
Again we find this conception of relative immanence in Plato. He transports
it, in a rather confused manner, into the cosmological order. He thinks, in
fact, that, if there are things great and good and beautiful, they are such
through a certain participation in the ideas of greatness, goodness, and beauty.
But this participation does not result from an emanation, an outflowing from the
Divinity into finite beings; it is only a reflection of the ideas, a
resemblance, which the reasonable being is in duty bound to perfect, as far as
possible, by his own energy. With Aristotle this notion of an immanent energy in
individuals acquires a new definiteness. The very exaggeration with which he
refuses to admit in God any efficient causality, as something unworthy of His
beatitude, leads him to place at the heart of finite being the principle of the
action which it puts forth with a view to that which is supremely lovable and
desirable. Now, according to him, these principles are individualized; their
development is limited; their orientation determined to a definite aim; and they
act upon one another. It is, therefore, a doctrine of relative immanence which
he maintains. After him the Stoics, reviving the physics of Heraclitus, came
back to a system of absolute immanence with their theory of germinal capacities.
The Alexandrian Fathers borrowed this term from them, taking out of it, however,
its pantheistic sense, when they set themselves to search in the writings of the
pagans for "the sparks of the light of the Word" (St. Justin), and, in human
souls, for the innate capacities which render the knowledge of God so easy and
so natural. St. Augustine, in his turn defines these capacities as "the active
and passive potentialities from which flow all the natural effects of beings",
and this theory he employs to demonstrate the real, but relative, immanence of
our intellectual and moral life.
Our natural desire to know and our spontaneous sympathies do not germinate in
us unless their seeds are in our soul. These are the first principles of reason,
the universal precepts of the moral consciousness. St. Thomas calls them
"habitus principiorum", "seminalia virtutum" "dispositiones naturales",
"inchoationes naturales". He sees in them the beginnings of all our
physiological, intellectual, and moral progress, and, following the course of
their development, he carries to the highest degree of precision the concept of
relative immanence. The Thomist tradition -- continuing after him the struggle
against empiricism and positivism on the one side and, on the other, against
rationalism carried to the extreme of monism -- has always defended the same
position. It recognizes the fact of immanence, but rejects every exaggeration on
either side.
(b) Actual Content of the Doctrine of Relative Immanence
This doctrine
rests upon that innermost experience which reveals to man his individuality,
that is to say his inward unity, his distinctness from his environment, and
which makes him conscious of his personality, that is to say, of his essential
independence with respect to the beings with which he is in relation. It,
moreover, avoids all imputation of monism, and the manner in which it conceives
of immanence harmonizes excellently with Catholic teaching. "An ejusmodi
immanentia Deum ab homine distinguat, necne? Si distinguit, quid tum a
catholica doctrina differt?" (Encycl. "Pascendi").
(i) God
God, then, transcends the world which He has created, and in
which He manifests His power. We know His works; through them we can demonstrate
His existence and find out many of His attributes. But the mysteries of His
inner life escape us; Trinity, Incarnation, Redemption are known to us only by
revelation, to which revelation the immanence of our rational and moral life
presents no obstacle whatever.
(ii) The World, Life, and the Soul
The organization of the world is
governed by Divine Providence, whose ordering action can be conceived in diverse
ways, whether we suppose successive interventions for the formation of various
beings, or whether, following St. Augustine, we prefer to maintain that God
created all things at the same time -- "Deus simul omnia creavit" (De Genesi ad
lit.). In the latter case we should invoke the hypothesis of germinal
capacities, according to which hypothesis God must have deposited in nature
energies of a determinate sort -- "Mundus gravidus est causis nascentium"
(ibid.) -- the evolution of which at favourable junctures of time would organize
the universe. This organization would be due to an immanent development, indeed,
but one proceeding under external influences. Thus did plants, animals, and men
appear in succession, though there could be no question of attributing to them a
common nature; on the contrary, the doctrine of relative immanence draws a sharp
line of demarcation between the various substances, and particularly between
matter and soul; it is extremely careful to maintain the independence of the
human person. Not only does this doctrine, joining issue with sensualism,
demonstrate that the mind is a living energy, which, far from letting itself be
absorbed by influences from without, forms its necessary and universal
principles by its own action under the pressure of experience -- not only this,
but it also safeguards the autonomy of human reason against that encroachment of
the Divine which the ontologists maintained.
(iii) Dogma and Moral
The human soul, then, enjoys an immanence and an
autonomy which are relative indeed but real, and which Divine Revelation itself
respects. Supernatural truth is, in fact, offered to an intelligence in full
possession of its resources, and the reasonable assent which we give to revealed
dogmas is by no means "a bondage" or "a limitation of the rights of thought". To
oppose Revelation with "a preliminary and comprehensive demurrer" ("une fin de
non-recevoir préliminaire et globale" -- Le Roy) in the name of the principle of
immanence, is to misinterpret that principle, which, rightly understood,
involves no such exigencies (see below, "The Method of Immanence"). Nor does the
fact of relative immanence stand in the way of progress in the understanding of
dogmas "in eodem sensu eademque sententia" (Conc. Vatic., sess. III). The human
soul, then, receives the Divine verities as the disciple receives his master's
teaching; it does not create those verities. Neither does it create principles
of moral conduct. The natural law is certainly not foreign to it, being graven
upon the very foundation of man's constitution. It lives in the heart of man.
This law is immanent to the human person, which consequently enjoys a certain
autonomy. No doubt it recognizes its relation to a transcendent legislator, but
none the less true is it that no prescription coming from another authority
would be accepted by the conscience if it was in opposition to the primordial
law, the requirements of which are only extended and clearly defined by positive
laws. In this sense the human will preserves its autonomy when, in obeying a
Divine law, it acts with a fundamentally inviolable liberty. This liberty,
however, may be aided by natural and supernatural helps. Conscious of its
weakness, it seeks and obtains the assistance of grace, but grace does not
absorb nature; it only adds to nature, and in no way infringes upon our
essential immanence.
B. Employment of the Method of Immanence
The notion of immanence
occupies so large a place in contemporary philosophy that many make an axiom of
it. It is held to be a directing principle of thought and Le Roy makes bold to
write that "to have acquired a clear consciousness of the principle of immanence
is the essential result of modern philosophy" (Dogme et Critique, 9). Now it is
in the name of this principle that "a preliminary and comprehensive demurrer"
(ibid.) is presented in bar of all Revelation, for in the light of it "a dogma
has the appearance of a subjection to bondage, a limitation of the rights of
thought, a menace of intellectual tyranny" (ibid.). And this creates a religious
situation with which apologetics is deeply concerned, and with good reason. All
the efforts of this science will be vain, all its arguments inconclusive, if it
cannot, first of all, compel minds imbued with the prejudice of absolute
immanence to take under consideration the problem of the transcendent. Without
this precaution, antinomy is inevitable: on the one hand, it is claimed, the
mind cannot receive a heterogeneous truth; on the other, revealed religion
proposes to us truths which go beyond the range of any finite intelligence. To
solve this difficulty we have recourse to the method of immanence. But this
method has been understood in two different ways which lead to diametrically
opposite results.
(1) Method Based on the Idea of Absolute Immanence
This is the
positivist and subjectivist method. It consists in accepting off-hand the
postulate of an absolute immanence of the rational and moral life. It is
therefore obliged to lower revealed truth to the level of scientific truths
which the mind attains solely by its own energy. Thus, some, like Lechartier,
have proposed to modify dogmatic formulæ and "dissolve the symbols" of them in
order to harmonize both with the aspirations of the soul which thinks them. By
this means "the higher realities, which religious myths have for so many
centuries striven to express, will be found identical with those which positive
science has just established". Revealed truth will then appear as coming from
us; it will present itself as the reflexion of our soul, which changes its
formulæ according as it can or cannot find itself in them. In this way there
will no longer be any antinomy, since human reason will be the principle of
dogmas. Others following Loisy, hope to find in themselves, through a
psychological analysis, the expression of revelation. This would be the outcome
of an immanent progress, "the consciousness which man has acquired of his
relations with God". Revelation is realized in man, but it is "the work of God
in him, with him, and by him ". Thus the difficulty arising out of the
opposition between the natural order and the supernatural would disappear -- but
at the price of a return to the doctrine of absolute immanence. It seems, too,
that Laberthonnière, though in spite of his principles, ends by accepting this
very same doctrine which he had undertaken to combat, when he writes that "since
our action is at once ours and God's, we must find in it the supernatural
element which enters into its constitution". According to this view,
psychological analysis will discover the Divine element immanent in our action,
the inward God "more present to us than we ourselves". Now this "living God of
conscience" can be discerned only through an intuition which we get by a sort of
moral and dynamic ontologism. But how will this presence of the Divine manifest
itself in us? By the true and imperative demand of our nature which calls for
the supernatural. -- Such is the abuse of the method of immanence which the
Encyclical "Pascendi gregis" points out and deplores: "And here again we have
reason for grievous complaint, because among Catholics there are to be found men
who, while repudiating the doctrine of immanence as a doctrine, make use of it
nevertheless for apologetic purposes, and do this so recklessly that they seem
to admit in human nature a genuine exigency properly so called in regard to the
supernatural order." With still less reserve, those whom the Encyclical calls
inteqralistœ boast of showing the unbeliever the supernatural germ which
has been transmitted to humanity from the consciousness of Christ, and hidden in
the heart of every man. This is the thought of Sabatier and of Buisson,
theologians of the liberal Protestant school -- "I am a man, and nothing Divine
is foreign to me" (Buisson).
(2) Method Based on the Idea of Relative Immanence
There is another
application of the method of immanence much more reserved than the one just
described since it keeps within the natural order and confines itself to stating
a philosophic problem, viz.: Is man sufficient for himself? or is he aware of
his insufficiency in such a way as to realize his need of some help from
without? Here we are not at all concerned -- as the Encyclical "Pascendi gregis"
reproaches the Modernists -- "with inducing the unbeliever to make trial of the
Catholic religion"; we are concerned only with;
- (1) compelling a man who analyzes his own being to break through the
circle within which, supposedly, the doctrine of immanence confines him, and
which makes him reject a priori, as out of the question, the whole argument of
objective apologetics; and then
- (2) with bringing him to recognize in his soul "a capacity and fitness for
the supernatural order which Catholic apologists, using the proper
reservations, have demonstrated" (Encycl. "Pascendi gregis").
In other words, this method has in itself nothing that calls for
condemnation. It consists, says Maurice Blondel, its inventor, "in equating
within our own consciousness, what we seem to think, to wish, and to do with
what we really do, wish and think, in such a way that in the fictitious
negations, or the ends artificially desired, those profound affirmations and
irrepressible needs which they imply shall still be found" (Lettre sur les
exigences). This method endeavours to prove that man cannot shut himself up in
himself, as in a little world which suffices unto itself. To prove this, it
takes an inventory of our immanent resources; it brings to light, on the one
hand, our irresistible aspirations towards the infinitely True, Good, and
Beautiful, and, on the other hand, the insufficiency of our means to attain
these ends. This comparison shows that our nature, left to itself, is not in a
state of equilibrium; that, to achieve its destiny, it needs a help which is
essentially beyond it -- a transcendent help. Thus, "a method of immanence
developed in its integrity becomes exclusive of a doctrine of immanence". In
fact, the internal analysis which it prescribes brings the human soul to
recognize itself as relative to a transcendent being, thereby setting before us
the problem of God. Nothing more is needed to make it evident that the
"preliminary and comprehensive demurrer", which it sought to set up against
Revelation in the name of the principle of immanence, is an unwarranted and
arrogant exaggeration. The psychologic examination of conscience which is just
now being made, far from ruling out the traditional apologetic, rather appeals
to it, opens the way for it, and demonstrates its necessity.
To this preliminary clearing of the ground the method adds a subjective
preparation which shall dispose the individual for the act of faith by exciting
in him the desire to enter into relations with the transcendent God. And the
result of this preparation will be not only intellectual and theoretical, but
also moral and practical. Arousing in him a more vivid consciousness of his
weakness and his need of help, the method will impel a man to acts of humility
which inspire prayer and attract grace.
Such is the twofold service which the method based on the idea of relative
immanence can render. Within these limits, it is rigorous. But could it not go
farther, and open to us a view of the nature of this transcendent being whose
existence it compels us to recognize? Might it not, for example, bring the
unbeliever to hear and heed "the appeal of preventive or sanctifying grace"
which would then express itself in psychologic facts discernible by observation
and philosophical analysis (Cardinal Dechamps)? Would it not enable us to
experience God, or at least "to find in our action the supernatural element
which is said to enter into His Constitution" (Père Laberthonnière)? Would it
not, finally, justify us in affirming with certainty that the object of our
"irrepressible aspirations" is a "supernatural Unnamed" (Blondel), an object
which is "beyond and above the natural order" (Ligeard)?
At this point the method of immanence stirs the delicate problem of the
relation between nature and the supernatural; but it is doubtful whether the
method can solve this problem by its immanent analysis. All the attempts
referred to above when they lead to anything, seem to do so only at the price of
confounding the notion of the transcendent with that of the preternatural, or
even of the supernatural -- or, again, at the price of confounding the Divine
co-operation and Divine grace. In a word, if the psychologic analysis of the
tendencies of human nature ends in "showing, without recourse to what Revelation
gives us, that man desires infinitely more than the natural order can give him"
(Ligeard), it does not follow that we can say with any certainty that this
"desired increase" is a supernatural Unnamed. As a matter of fact,
- (1) the natural order far exceeds in vastness the object of my analysis;
- (2) between my nature and the supernatural there is the preternatural;
- (3) the aids to which my nature aspires, and which God gives me, are not
necessarily of the supernatural order.
Besides, even if a supernatural action does in fact manifest itself under
these religious aspirations, immanent analysis, apprehending only psychological
phenomena, cannot detect it. But the question is still under consideration; it
is not for us to solve the mystery of the transcendent in a definitive manner
and from the point of view of the method of immanence.
Bibliography
MYERS, Human Personality and its Survival of Bodily
Death (London, 1903); PRINCE, Dissociation of Personality (New York,
1906); JAMES, Varieties of Religious Experience (New York, 1902);
THAMIRY, De rationibus seminalibus et Immanentia (Lille, 1905); SABATIER,
Esquisse d'une philosophie de la religion . . . (Paris, 1898); BUISSON,
La Religion, la Morale et la Science (Paris, 1904); LOISY, Autour d'un
petit livre (Paris, 1904); LABERTHONNIÈRE, Essais de philosophie
religieuse (Paris, 1904); LE ROY, Dogme et critique (Paris, 1907);
MAISONNEUVE in VACANT, Dict. de théologie catholique, s. v.
Apologétique; BERTHELOT, La science et la morale (Revue de Paris,
1 February, 1895); BOURGEOIS, Solidarité (Paris, 1903); SAINT AUGUSTINE,
De Genesi ad litteram in P. L., XLVII; de Trinitate in
P. L., XLII; BLONDEL, Lettre sur les exigences de la pensée
contemporaine en matière d'apologétique (Saint-Dizier, 1896); DECHAMPS,
Entretien (Mechlin, 1860); LIGEARD, La théologie catholique et la
transcendance du surnaturel (Paris, 1908); THAMIRY, Les deux aspects de
l'immanence et le problème religieux (Paris, 1908); MICHELET, Dieu et
l'agnosticisme contemporain (Paris, 1909); ILLINWORTH, Divine
Immanence (London, 1898).
E. Thamiry
The Catholic Encyclopedia, Volume VII
Also, an entirely different concept is:
Imminence
The individual articles presented here were generally first published in the
early 1980s. This subject presentation was first placed on the Internet in May
1997.
Copyright Information
Send an e-mail question or comment to us: E-mail
The main BELIEVE web-page (and the index to subjects) is at http://mb-soft.com/believe/indexaz.html