I shall begin by referring to one of my
masters, the great Marxist philosopher, Louis Althusser. For Althusser, the
birth of Marxism was not a simple thing. It was composed of two revolutions, two
major intellectual events. First, a scientific one. This event was Marx's
creation of a science of history, the name of which is "historical materialism".
The second event was of a philosophical nature. It was the creation, by Marx and
others, of a new trend, the name of which is « dialectical materialism ». We can
say that a new philosophy is required to clarify and assist the birth of a new
science. Plato's philosophy was likewise required by the beginning of
mathematics, or Kant's philosophy by the Newtonian physics. There is after all
no difficulty in all of this. In this framework it is possible to say two things
about the development of philosophy.
1. This development was dependent on
new facts in some fields which are not immediately of a philosophical nature.
Particularly on facts in the fields of science. Such as mathematics for Plato,
Descartes or Leibniz, physics for Kant, Whitehead or Popper, history for Hegel
or Marx, biology for Nietzsche, Bergson or Deleuze.
As far as I am
concerned, I quite agree that philosophy depends on some non- philosophical
fields. And I have called these fields the "conditions" of philosophy. I would
simply like to say that I do not limit the conditions of philosophy to the
progress of science. I propose a much larger set of conditions, under four
possible types: science, but also, politics, art, an love. So my own work
depends, for instance, on a new mathematical concept of the infinite, but also
on new forms of revolutionary politics, on the great poems of Mallarmé, Rimbaud,
Pessoa, Mandelstam or Wallace Stevens, on the prose of Samuel Beckett, on the
new ways of love which have emerged in the context of psychoanalysis and the
complete transformation of all questions concerning sexuation and
gender.
It would therefore be possible for me to say that the development
of philosophy is the gradual adaptation of philosophy to the change in its
conditions. Then you could say : Philosophy is always behind! Philosophy is
always trying to catch up with non- philosophical novelties! And I would have to
say: correct! That was in fact Hegel's conclusion. Philosophy is the bird of
wisdom, and the bird of wisdom is the owl. But the owl flies off only when the
day is over. Philosophy is the discipline which comes after the day of
knowledge, the day of experiences, at the beginning of the night. And apparently
our problem, the problem of the development of philosophy, is solved. There are
two cases. First case: a new morning of creative experiences in science,
politics, art or love is coming. And we shall have a new evening for philosophy.
Second case: our civilization is exhausted, and the only future we can imagine
is a dark one, a future of perpetual dusk. So the future of philosophy will be
its slow death, its slow death in the night. Philosophy will be reduced to what
we can read at the beginning of a beautiful text by Samuel Beckett,
Company: "A voice is speaking in the dark." A voice without meaning,
without destination.
And in fact, from Hegel and Auguste Comte to
Nietzsche, Heidegger or Derrida, not to mention Wittgenstein and Carnap, we can
find the philosophical idea of a probable death of philosophy, in any case in
its classical form, the metaphysical one.
I could stop my lecture here,
and say with my hair standing straight up on my head like a singer in the Punk
style: no future! After that we would all drink the alcohol of
nihilism.
But there remain some little difficulties.
The first
one, which is perhaps too formal, perhaps a sophistry, is that the idea of the
end of philosophy has been a typical philosophical idea for a long time.
Moreover, it is often a positive idea. For Hegel, philosophy is at its end
because philosophy can finally understand what an absolute knowledge is. For
Marx, philosophy as an interpretation of the world can be replaced by a concrete
transformation of this same world. For Nietzsche, the negative abstraction of
old philosophy has to be destroyed to liberate a true vital affirmation, a big
"Yes!" to all that exists. And for the analytical current, metaphysical
sentences, which are pure nonsense, have to be deconstructed in favor of clear
propositions and arguments under the paradigm of modem logic.
In all
these cases we see that the great declarations concerning the death of
philosophy in general, and of metaphysics in particular, are most probably a
rhetorical means of introducing a new way, or a new goal, into philosophy
itself. The best means of saying: I am a new philosopher, is probably to say:
philosophy is finished, philosophy is dead. So I propose to begin something
absolutely new. Not philosophy, but thinking! Not philosophy, but vital potency!
Not philosophy, but a new rational language! In fact: not old philosophy, but my
own new philosophy.
So there is a possibility that the development of
philosophy must always be in the form of resurrection. The old philosophy, like
the old man, is dead, but this death is in fact the birth of the new man, the
new philosopher.
But as you know, there is a close relationship between
resurrection and immortality, between the greatest change we can imagine, the
change from death into life, and the most complete absence of change we can
think of, when we are in the joy of salvation.
Maybe the repetition of
the theme of the end of metaphysics and the correlative repetitive theme of a
new beginning of thinking is the sign of a fundamental immobility of philosophy
as such. Maybe philosophy has to put its continuity, its repetitive nature in
the form of the dramatic couple of death and birth.
At this point we can
return to the work of Louis Althusser. Because Althusser, who maintains that
philosophy is dependent on science, also maintains something very strange, which
is that philosophy has no history at all, that philosophy is always the same
thing. In this case, the problem of the development of philosophy is an easy
one: the future of philosophy is its past.
It sounds nearly like a joke
to see the great Marxist Althusser as the last defender of the old scholastic
conception of a philosophia perennis, of philosophy as pure repetition of
the same; philosophy in the Nietzchean style as an eternal return of the
same.
But what is this "same"? What is the sameness of the same, which
returns in the a-historical destiny of philosophy? Behind this question we
naturally find an old discussion about the true nature of philosophy. There are
roughly two main tendencies. For the first one philosophy is essentially a
reflexive knowledge. The knowledge of truth in theoretical fields, the knowledge
of values in practical fields. We have to organize learning and the transmission
of knowledge. And the appropriate form of philosophy is that of a school. The
philosopher is a professor, like Kant, Hegel, Husserl, Heidegger and so many
others., including myself, when you address me under the name of "Professor
Badiou ".
The second possibility is that philosophy is not really a
knowledge, that it is neither theoretical nor practical. It lies in the direct
transformation of a subject, it is a kind of radical conversion, a complete
change of life. And consequently it is very near religion, but by exclusively
rational means; very near love, but without the violent support of desire; very
near political engagement, but without the constraint of a centralized
organization; very near the potency of artistic creation, but without the
physical means of art; very near scientific knowledge, but without the formalism
of mathematics, and without the empirical and technical means of physics. For
this second tendency philosophy is not by necessity a matter of school,
learning, transmission and professors. It is a free address of anybody to
everybody. Like Socrates speaking to young men in the streets of Athens; like
Descartes writing letters to Princess Elizabeth ; like Jean-Jacques Rousseau
writing his confessions ; or also the Nietzsche or the novels or Sartre plays;
or like, if you forgive me for a narcissistic touch, my own novels and
plays.
The difference is that philosophy is no longer knowledge, or
knowledge of knowledge. It is an action. One could say that what identifies
philosophy is not the rules of a discourse, but the singularity of an act. It is
this act that the enemies of Socrates called: "the corruption of young people ".
And because of that, as you know, Socrates was sentenced to death. "To corrupt
young people" is after all not a bad name for the philosophical act. If you
properly understand "to corrupt". Here "to corrupt" means to teach the
possibility of refusing any blind submission to established opinions. To corrupt
is to give to young people some means of changing their minds about all social
norms ; to corrupt is to substitute discussion and rational criticism for
imitation, and even, if the question is a question of principles, to substitute
revolt for obedience. But this revolt is neither spontaneous nor agressive
inasmuch as it is a consequence of principles and rational critics. In the poems
of the great trench poet Arthur Rimbaud we find the strange expression: "Logical
Revolts". That is probably a good definition of the philosophical act. "Logical
Revolts". It is not by chance that my friend, the very good philosopher Jacques
Rancière created a very important magazine in the seventies, the title of which
was precisely: "Logical Revolts".
But if the very essence of philosophy
is an active one, we can have a better understanding of the reason why, for
Louis Althusser, there does not exist a real history of philosophy. In his own
work Althusser himself proposes to say that the function of philosophy is to
introduce a division into opinions. And more precisely, into opinions about
scientific knowledge, or, more generally, into theoretical activities. What kind
of division? Ultimately, the division between materialism and idealism. And
since he was a Marxist, Althusser thought that materialism is the revolutionary
framework for theoretical activities, and that idealism is the conservative one.
So his final definition was: philosophy is like a political struggle in the
theoretical field itself.
But apart from the Marxist conclusion, we can
observe two points:
First. The philosophical act is always in the form of
a decision, a separation, a clear distinction. Between knowledge and opinion,
between correct opinions and false opinions, between truth and falsity, between
Good and Evil, between, wisdom and madness, and so on.
Second. The
philosophical act always has a normative dimension. The division is also a
hierarchy. In the Marxist case materialism is the good term and idealism the bad
term. But more generally, it always appears that the division of concepts or the
division of experiences is in fact the act of imposing, perhaps, on young
people, a new hierarchy. And negatively, the result of the act is the reversal
of an established order, or of an old hierarchy.
So we have effectively
something invariant in philosophy, something like a compulsive repetition, or
like the eternal return of the same. We can summarize this matrix, which is not
unrelated to the notorious series of the Matrix movies.
Philosophy
is the act of reorganizing all theoretical and practical experiences, by
proposing a new great normative division, which reverses an established
intellectual order, and promotes new values beyond the common ones. The form of
all this is a more or less free address to everybody, but first and foremost to
young people, because a philosopher knows perfectly well that young people have
to make decisions about their lives, and that they are often better disposed to
accepting the risks of a Logical Revolt.
All this explains why philosophy
is in some sense always the same thing. Naturally, every philosopher thinks that
his or her work is completely new. That's only human. And many historians of
philosophy have introduced absolute ruptures. For instance, after Kant,
classical metaphysics was said to be impossible. Or, after Wittgenstein, it was
no longer possible to forget that the study of language is the core of
philosophy. So we have a rationalist turn, a critical turn, a linguistic turn...
But in fact, nothing in philosophy is irreversible. There is no absolute turn.
Many philosophers can find today, in Plato or in Leibniz, some points which are
for them more interesting, more active than similar points in Heidegger or
Wittgenstein. It is because their own matrix is largely identical to that of
Plato or Leibniz. The fact that philosophy is largely a repetition of its act
clarifies the immanent affinities between philosophers. Deleuze with Leibniz and
Spinoza; Sartre with Descartes and Hegel; Merleau-Ponty with Bergson and
Aristotle ; I, myself, with Plato and Hegel; Slavoj Zizek with Kant and
Schelling... And maybe, for almost three thousand years, everybody with
everybody.
But if the philosophical act is formally the same, and the
return of the same, we have to take into account the change of the historical
context. Because the act takes place under some conditions. When a philosopher
proposes a new division and a new hierarchy for the experiences of his time, it
is because a new intellectual creation, a new truth, has just appeared. It is in
fact because, in his eyes, we have to assume the consequences of a new event in
the real conditions of philosophy.
For example, Plato proposed the
division between the sensible and the intelligible under the condition of
geometry and of a post-Pythagorean concept of number and measure. Hegel
introduced history and becoming into the Absolute Idea, because of the striking
novelty of the French revolution. Nietzsche developed a dialectical relationship
between Greek tragedy and the birth of philosophy in the context of the
tumultuous feeling caused by the discovery of Richard Wagner's musical drama.
And Derrida transformed the classical approach of rigid metaphysical oppositions
partly because of the growing and irreducible importance, in our experiences, of
their female dimension.
That's why we can speak finally of a creative
repetition. There is something unchanging in the form of a gesture, a gesture of
division. And there is, with the pressure of some events and their consequences,
the necessity for transforming some aspects of the philosophical gesture. So we
have a form, and we have the variable form of the unique form. That's why we
clearly recognize philosophy and philosophers, despite their enormous
differences and despite their violent conflicts. Kant said that the history of
philosophy was a battlefield. Yes, it is so! But it is also the repetition of
the same battle, on the same field. Perhaps a musical image may help. The
development of philosophy is in the classical form of theme and variations.
Repetition, the theme, and constant novelty, the variations.
But both
theme and variations come after some events in politics, art, science, love,
events which provide the necessity for a new variation for the same theme. So
we, philosophers, are working during the night, after the day of real becoming
of a new truth. I am reminded of a beautiful poem of Wallace Stevens, Man
carrying thing. Stevens writes: "We must endure our thoughts all night."
Alas! That is the destiny of philosophers and philosophy. And Stevens continues:
"Until the bright obvious stands motionless in cold." Yes, we hope, we believe,
that one day, the "bright obvious" will "stand motionless".
The "bright
obvious" of the Idea will stand like a fixed star in the sky, "motionless in
cold". It will be the final stage of philosophy, the absolute Idea, the complete
revelation... But that will never happen. On the contrary, when something
happens in the day of living truths, we have to repeat the philosophical act,
and to create a new variation.
So the future of philosophy is, like its
past, a creative repetition. We must endure our thoughts all night
forever.
The philosopher is useful, because he or she has the task of
observing the morning of a truth, and of interpreting this new truth over
against old opinions. If « we must endure our thoughts all night», it is because
we must correctly corrupt young people. When we feel that a truth-event
interrupts the continuity of ordinary life, we have to say to others: "Wake up!
The time of new thinking and acting is here!" But for that, we ourselves must be
awake. We, philosophers, are not allowed to sleep. A philosopher is a poor night
watchman.
© lacan.com 1997/2006
Copyright Notice. Please respect the
fact that this material in LACAN.COM is copyright.
Available only through
EBSCO Publishing. Inc.
It is made available here without charge for personal
use only. It may not be stored, displayed, published, reproduced, or used for
any other purpose.