|
Deleuze always paid
tribute to Sartre as the figure who, during the thirties and forties, woke
French philosophy from its academic slumbers. He considered the 1937
article, 'The Transcendence of the Ego', the origin of everything: why? It
is because, in this text, Sartre proposes the idea - I am citing Deleuze -
of 'an impersonal transcendental field, having the form neither of a
personal synthetic consciousness nor subjective identity-the subject, to
the contrary, always being constituted.' I want to emphasize this remark
of Deleuze's all the more insofar as the motif of an impersonal
transcendental field is dominant throughout my Greater Logic, where it is
effectuated, in the finest technical detail, as a logic of appearance or
worlds.
Deleuze remarked also that Sartre had been prevented from
thinking all of the consequences of his idea because he had attached the
impersonal field to a (self)-consciousness. This is absolutely correct. We
could also say: Sartre continued to believe in an auto-unification of the
transcendental. He did not expose the subject to the alea of a pure
Outside. Now, one of the names of the Outside is 'event'. This is why the
event, as that to which the power (puissance) of a thought is
devoted, and/ or that from which this power proceeds, has, after Sartre,
become a common term for the greater number of contemporary philosophers.
Other than through the critique of the phenomenology of consciousness,
this term has been transmitted to us, on the side of truth-procedures, by
the lasting fragment-in the 20th century-of four entangled motifs: that,
in politics, of Revolution; in love, of erotic liberation; in the arts, of
performance; and in the sciences, of the epistemological break. In
philosophy, it can discerned as well in Wittgenstein ('The world is
everything which happens') as in Heidegger (being as being-on-the-way,
Ereignis).
The idea is central in Deleuze, as it is in my
own enterprise-but what a contrast! The interest of this contrast is that
it exposes the original ambiguity of the idea itself. It effectively
contains a dimension of structure (interruption as such, the appearance of
a supernumerary term) and a dimension of the history of life (the
concentration of becoming, being as coming-to-self, promise). In the first
case, the event is disjoined from the One, it is separation, assumption of
the void, pure non-sense. In the second case, it is the play of the One,
composition, intensity of the plenum, the crystal (or logic) of sense.
The Logic of Sense is the most considerable effort on the part of
Gilles Deleuze to clarify his concept of the event. He does so in the
company of the Stoics, they for whom the 'event' must be integrated into
the inflexible discipline of the All, according to which Stoicism orients
itself. Between 'event' and 'destiny', there must be something like a
subjective reciprocation.
I will extract from The Logic of
Sense what I will call the four Deleuzean axioms of the
event.
Axiom 1: "Unlimited becoming becomes the event
itself."
The event is the ontological realisation of the eternal
truth of the One, the infinite power (puissance) of Life. It is in
no way a void, or a stupor, separated from what becomes. To the contrary,
it is the concentration of the continuity of life, its intensification.
The event is that which donates the One to the concatenation of
multiplicities. We could advance the following formula: in becomings, the
event is the proof of the One of which these becomings are the expression.
This is why there is no contradiction between the limitless of becoming
and the singularity of the event. The event reveals in an immanent way the
One of becomings, it makes becoming this One. The event is the becoming of
becoming: the becoming(-One) of (unlimited) becoming.
Axiom
2: "The event is always that which has just happened and that which is
about to happen, but never that which is happening."
The event is a
synthesis of past and future. In reality, the expression of the One in
becomings is the eternal identity of the future as a dimension of the
past. The ontology of time, for Deleuze as for Bergson, admits no figure
of separation. Consequently, the event would not be what takes place
'between' a past and a future, between the end of a world and the
beginning of another. It is rather encroachment and connection: it
realises the indivisible continuity of Virtuality. It exposes the unity of
passage which fuses the one-just-after and the one-just-before. It is not
'that which happens', but that which, in what happens, has become and will
become. The event as event of time, or time as the continued and eternal
procedure of being, introduces no division into time, no intervallic void
between two times. 'Event' repudiates the present understood as either
passage or separation; it is the operative paradox of becoming. This
thesis can thus be expressed in two ways: there is no present (the event
is re-represented, it is active immanence which co-presents the past and
the future); or, everything is present (the event is living or chaotic
eternity, as the essence of time).
Axiom 3: "The event is of
a different regime than the actions and passions of the body, even if it
results from them."
Whether thought of as the becoming of
becomings, or as disjunctive eternity, the event intensifies bodies,
concentrates their constitutive multiplicity. It would therefore be
neither of the same nature as the actions and the passions of the body,
nor supervene on them. The event is not identical to the bodies which it
affects, but neither is it transcendent to what happens to them or what
they do, such that it cannot be said any longer that they are
(ontologically) different to bodies. It is the differenciator of actions
and passions of the body as a result. What then is an immanent One of
becomings, if not Becoming? Or difference, or Relation (other Deleuzean
terms)? However, Becoming is not an idea, but what becomings become. Thus
the event affects bodies, because it is what they do or support as exposed
syntheses. It is the coming of the One through them that they are as
distinct nature (virtual rather than actual) and homogenous result
(without them, it is not). This is the sense that must be given to the
formula: 'The event is coextensive with becoming'. The event of Life will
be thought as the body without organs: of a different regime than living
organisms, but uniquely deployed or legible as the result of the actions
and passions of these organisms.
Axiom 4: "A life is
composed of a single and same Event, lacking all the variety of what
happens to it."
What is difficult here is not the reiteration of
the One as the concentrated expression of vital deployment. The three
preceeding axioms are clear on this point. The difficulty is in
understanding the word 'composed'. The event is what composes a life
somewhat as a musical composition is organised by its theme. 'Variety'
must here be understood as 'variation', as variation on a theme. The event
is not what happens to a life, but what is in what happens, or what
happens in what happens, such that it can only have a single Event. The
Event, in the disparate material of a life, is precisely the Eternal
Return of the identical, the undifferentiated power (puissance) of
the Same: the 'powerful inorganic life.' With regard to any multiplicity
whatsoever, it is of the essence of the Event to compose them into the One
that they are, and to exhibit this unique composition in a potentially
infinite variety of ways.
With these four axioms, Deleuze reveals
his response to evental ambiguity: he chooses for destiny. The event is
not the risky (hasardeux) passage from one state of things to
another. It is the immanent stigmata of a One-result of all becomings. In
the multiple-which-becomes, in the between-two of the multiples which are
active multiples, the event is the destiny of the One.
It is enough
to invert these four axioms-here as in Book II (of Logiques des
mondes), 'inversion' reveals negations-in order to obtain a quite good
axiomatic of what I call 'event', that which is a site, appearing in
maximal intensity, and equally capable of making absolute its own
inexistence in apparition (l'apparaître).
Axiom 1. An
event is never the concentration of a vital continuity, or the immanent
intensification of a becoming. It is never coextensive with becoming. It
is, on the contrary, on the side of a pure break with the becoming of an
object of the world, through the auto-apparition of this object.
Correlatively, it is the supplementation of apparition
(l'apparaître) by the emergence (surgissement) of a trace:
what formerly inexisted becomes intense existence.
There is, with
regard to the continuity in the becomings of the world, at once a lack
(the impossibility of auto-apparition with the interruption of the
authority of the mathematical laws of being and the logical laws of
appearance) and an excess (the impossibility of the emergence of a maximal
intensity of existence). 'Event' names the conjunction of this lack and
this excess.
Axiom 2. The event would not be the inseperable
encroachment of the past on the future, or the eternally past being of the
future. It is, to the contrary, a vanishing mediator, an intemporal
instant which renders disjunct the previous state of an object (the site)
and the state that follows. We could equally say that the event extracts
from a time the possibility of an other time. This other time, whose
materiality envelops the consequences of the event, deserves the name of a
new present. The event is neither past nor future. It makes us present to
the present.
Axiom 3. The event would not be the result of
the actions and passions of a body, nor does it differ in nature from
them. To the contrary, an active and adequate body in a new present is an
effect of the event, as we have seen in detail in Book IV (of Logique
des mondes). We must here reverse Deleuze-in the sense in which, after
Nietzsche, he himself wanted to reverse Plato. These are not the actions
and passions of the multiples which are, under the title of an immanent
result, synthesised in the event. It is the blow of an evental One which
animates multiplicities and forms them into a subjectivisable body. And
the trace of an event, which is itself incorporated in the new present, is
clearly of the same nature as the actions of this body.
Axiom 4.
An event does not make a composite unity of what is. There is, to the
contrary, a decomposition of worlds by multiple evental sites.
Just
as it performs a separation of times, the event is separated from other
events. Truths are multiple, and multiform. They are exceptions in their
worlds, and not the One which makes them converge. Deleuze often adopts
the Leibnizian principle of Harmony, even as he defends the idea of
divergent series and incompossible worlds. The eternal and unique Event is
the focal point at which the ingredients of a life converge. Beyond the
'chaosmos' in which the divergent series and heteroclite multiplicities
are effectuated, 'nothing but the Event subsists, the Event alone,
Eventum Tantum for all contraries, which communicates witih itself
through its own distance, resonating across all its disjuctions.' No, this
'resonance' does not attract me. I propose rather a flat sound, without
resonance, which in no way modifies the the apparition of a site, and
nothing is disposed in harmony-or in disharmony-either with itself
(considered as subsisting solitude) or with others (considered as the
reabsorption of contraries). There is not-there cannot be-a 'Unique event
of which all the others are shreds and fragments.' The one of a truth is
initiated on the basis of the without-One of the event, its contingent
dissemination.
This dispute is without a doubt, as Lyotard would
say, a differend, since it bears on the fundamental semantic connection of
the word 'event': with sense for Deleuze, and with truth for me. Deleuze's
formula is without apology: 'The event, which is to say, sense.' From the
beginning of his book, he forges what is for me a chimera, an inconsistent
neologism: the 'sense-event.' Such a claim communicates with the
linguistic turn of the great contemporary sophists, much more than Deleuze
would have wished. In maintaining that the event belongs to the register
of sense, the entire project finds its ground on the side of language.
Consider: 'The event is sense itself. The event belongs essentially to
language, it is in an essential rapport with language.' It would be
necessary to detail the dramatic reactive consequences of this kind of
statement, and of many others: for example, '[The event] is the pure
expressed in what happens which makes us signify.' Here is the kernel of
the aestheticisation of everything, and the expressive politics of the
'multitudes', in which the compact thought of the Master is today
dispersed. Insofar as it is the localised disfunction of the
transcendental of a world, the event does not have the least sense, nor is
it sense itself. If it only remains as trace, it can in no way be
supported on the side of language. It only opens a space of consequences
in which the body of a truth is composed. Like every real point, as Lacan
saw, it is absolutely on the side of this unsensed which by itself can
only maintain a rapport with language by making a hole in it. And nothing
sayable, nothing of the order of the transcendental laws of language
(du dire), can fill this hole.
Like all philosophers of
vital continuity, Deleuze cannot abide any division between sense, the
transcendental law of appearance, and truths, eternal exceptions. He even
seems sometimes to identify the two. He once wrote to me that he 'felt no
need for the category of truth. He was certainly justified in such a
claim: sense is a name sufficient for truth. There are, however, perverse
effects of this identification. Vitalist logic, which submits the
actualisation of multiplicities to the order of the virtual One-All,
overlooks the fact that, in the simultaneous declaration that events are
sense, and that they have, as Deleuze proclaims, 'an eternal truth,' we
find religion in its pure state. If sense has in effect an eternal truth,
then God exists, having never been anything other than the truth of sense.
Deleuze's idea of the event would have had to convince him to follow
Spinoza to the end, he who Deleuze elects as 'the Christ of philosophers,'
and convince him to name 'God' the unique Event in which becomings are
diffracted. Lacan knew well that to deliver that which happens over to
sense is to work towards the subjective consolidation of religion, since,
as he wrote, 'the stability of religion is provided by sense, which is
always religious.'
This latent religiosity is all too apparent in
the disciples eager to praise the supposed inverse and constituant moment
of an unbridled Capital, the 'creativity' of the multitudes: those who
believe they have seen-or what they call seeing-a planetary
Parousia of a communism of 'forms of life' in the
anti-globalisation demonstrations in Seattle or Genoa, in which
disaffected (désoeuvrée) youths participate in their own way in the
sinister meetings of the financial establishment. Deleuze, often sceptical
towards the formulations of those concerned with political matters, would
have, I believe, laughed to himself about such pathos. Having openly
conceptualised the place of the event in the multiform procedures of
thought, Deleuze had to reduce this place to what he called 'the ideal
singularities which communicate in a single and same Event.' If
'singularity' is inevitable, the other terms are of dubious value. 'Ideal'
could be taken as 'eternal' if Deleuze was not overly obsessed with the
real of the event. 'Communicate' could be taken as 'universal' if Deleuze
did not interdict any interruption of communication which would
immediately connect any rupture to transcendental continuity. Of the
'single and same,' I have already noted its unfortunate nature: the effect
of a One, on bodies, of an evental blow (frappe) is necessarily
transformed by the absorption of the event by the One of
life.
Deleuze has very strongly marked the nature of the
philosophical combat in which the destiny of the word 'event' is played
out: 'A double struggle has as its object the prevention of every dogmatic
confusion between event and essence, and also every empiricist confusion
between event and accident.' There is nothing to add. Except that, when he
thinks the event as intensified result and continuity of becoming, Deleuze
is an empiricist (which he, in any case, continually proclaimed). And
that, when he reincorporates it into the One of 'the unlimited Aion, the
Infinitive in which it subsists and insists', into the always-there of the
Virtual, he is tendentially dogmatic.
To break with empiricism, the
event must be thought as the advent of what is subtracted from all
experience: the ontologically un-founded and the transcendentally
discontinuous. To break with dogmatism, the event must be released from
every tie to the One. It must be subtracted from Life in order to be
released to the stars.
The
original French text is "L'événement selon Deleuze" in Alain Badiou,
Logiques des mondes (Paris: Seuil, 2006).
|
|