Politics and FriendshipA Discussion with Jacques Derrida |
Geoffrey Bennington:
It's a great pleasure and honour for me to welcome Jacques Derrida on behalf
of the
University of Sussex, and more especially on behalf of the Centre for
Modern French
Thought. This is the second time in the last five years
or so that Jacques Derrida has
visited us, and I know from the many
reactions I've had how lucky people feel about that.
I'm not going to make a
speech of any sort about who Jacques Derrida is or what claims
he might have
on our interest; I take your presence here in such numbers to be sufficient
grounds for thinking that you're clear enough about that anyway, so I'll
just make some
brief remarks to leave us much time as possible for us to
listen to Jacques Derrida. The
format that we've agreed for the
session is as follows: I will speak for five minutes or so
and suggest three
or four preliminary areas of discussion to which Jacques Derrida will
respond, under this general topic of politics and friendship, which as many
of you will
know gives its title to a book recently published in English (it
was published in French in
1994), and I expect many of you will have read
it. So, I'll initially suggest three or four
lines of inquiry to give
an opportunity for Jacques Derrida to sketch out some of the main
lines of
argument in the book and after his responses to that invitation he will be happy
to
take questions from you. I would like to suggest for the earlier
part of the session, and we
are severely limited by time, that we try to
remain at least broadly within the ambit of
these initial themes that come
out of the book.
I've got four lines of questioning which are simple, and simply openings to
discussion on
the basis of the book Politics of Friendship. The first
one is the question: 'Why politics?'.
You've obviously been the object of a
demand for politics or a demand for a politics for
years from many sides,
and it might be thought that this book is finally answering that
demand. So, are you now elaborating, some people would say finally
elaborating, a
political theory or a deconstructive politics? Second
question, or line of questioning,
equally straightforward: 'Why
friendship?' The book is called Politics of Friendship, and
it might
seem strange to approach political arguments through the apparently marginal
concept of friendship rather than through more obvious concepts such as
sovereignty,
power, legitimacy, representation, and so on. In other
words, what has friendship got to
do with politics, and what has politics
got to do with friendship? Third question or line of
questioning is
about a word or a concept that appears insistently throughout the book, and
that's the word or concept democracy - and more specifically in the
formulation, which is
repeated throughout the book, of a 'democracy to
come'. I wonder if you could tell us
something about that and what it
might mean. And the last line of questioning, which is
really an
opening onto work that you have done since the publication of this book in
French in 1994, is based on the observation that that more recent work has
tended to
move the, or seems to have moved the centre of gravity of this
type of political or quasi-
political investigation towards the concept of
hospitality. You have published a lot of
work in recent years around
the concept of hospitality: I wonder if you might be able to
give us some
sense of what that involves, perhaps around the situation here today where
we're offering you something like hopitality, we're welcoming you more or
less hospitably
into our more or less domestic space which is itself
enclosed in a national or cultural space
which hasn't always been, and still
often isn't, very hospitable to your work. So, four
questions: 1) Why
politics?; 2) Why friendship?; 3) What about democracy?; 4) What
about
hospitality?
Jacques Derrida:
I have thirty minutes today. Thank you, I'm very grateful and I'm
pleased and honoured to
be back here, and especially to be associated with
this new Centre for Modern French
Thought which I think, and I'm not the
only one to think that, is a very important and
necessary initiative.
We all look forward to its success and we'll try to do our best to
participate in it.
Now, as you can imagine these questions are all the more difficult because I
have to really
improvise in English in a few minutes a straightforward
response, and not knowing if some
of you have read or not the texts that are
more accurate and explicit than what I could say
here. So, I'll try to
adjust a minimal and straightforward response to Geoff's questions.
1. Why Politics?
It is true that, from the beginning, so to speak, when I started writing and
teaching, many
people, friendly and unfriendly, reproached me with not
directly addressing political
questions. I think that it was at the
same time both an unfair and fair objection. Unfair
because I think
everything I did was directly or indirectly connected with political
questions, and I could show this in a very precise manner. But it is
true and it is a fair
objection to the extent that this relation to politics
was very indirect and very elliptical,
and waiting for a moment in the
development of my work when the level I wanted to
reach in this
re-elaboration of the political question could be reached; and this accounts for
the delay, for the implicit fashion I addressed this question at the
beginning.
Now, to take literally Geoff's question which I have in front of me: I don't
think that even
now I am answering the demand for politics, that is to
propose something which could fit
into what one calls in our tradition,
politics. What I am trying to do now, especially in the
books Spectres
of Marx or in the Politics of Friendship, is to try to understand or to re-
think, I'm not the only one doing that of course, but to try with others to
re-think what the
political is, what is involved precisely in the
dissemination of the political field. So, I'm not
proposing a new
political content within the old frame but trying to re-define, or to think
differently, what is involved in the political as such, and for the very
same reason I don't
propose a political theory because what I'm saying,
specifically on friendship and
hospitality, on what friendship is and what
hospitality is, exceeds, precisely, knowledge.
In its extreme and more
essential form it has to do with something which cannot become a
theoreme,
it is something which simply has to be known, there is some type of experience,
of political experience in friendship and hospitality which cannot be simply
the object of a
theory. Which is not an anti-theoretical move; I think
political theory is necessary, but I
try to articulate this necessity of a
political theory with something in politics or in
friendship, in
hospitality, which cannot, for structural reasons, become the object of
knowledge, of a theory, of a theoreme.
So, it's not a political theory - part of what I'm trying to say in these
texts is not part of a
theory that would be included in the field known as
politology or political theory, and it's
not a deconstructive politics
either. I don't think that there is such a thing as a
deconstructive
politics, if by the name 'politics' we mean a programme, an agenda, or even
the name of a regime. We will see even the word democracy, which I try
to locate, is not
simply the name of a political regime or nation-state
organisation. So, I don't think that
what I'm engaged in, what I have
been trying to do in a very complicated way for a long
time, can be called
political theory or deconstructive politics, but I think that given - or
supposing that they are given - the premises of what I have been doing
before these last
books, the time has come for me to say something more
about politics. Not simply a
political theory, a deconstructive
politics, but to say something about politics is again not
simply a
speculative gesture: it's a concrete and personal commitment, and this
performative commitment is part of what I'm writing. Spectres of Marx,
before being a
text about Marx's theory, Marx's heritage, is, let's say, a
personal commitment at a certain
moment, in a certain form, in a singular
fashion.
2. Why friendship?
Why then - the second question - this privilege granted, within this field
that I have just
described, to friendship? Geoff says, rightly so,
that friendship has been an apparently
marginal concept within the field of
politics and of political philosophy for centuries. It is
true and not
so true - it is marginal in the usual taxonomies of political concepts.
You
can't find the concept of friendship there; usually it's left to ethics
or psychology or morals,
but it's not considered a political concept as
government, or sovereignty, or citizenship
may be considered
political. But as soon as you read the canonical texts in political theory
starting with Plato or Aristotle you discover that friendship plays an
organising role in the
definition of justice, of democracy even. I
quote in the Politics of Friendship many texts
of Plato and Aristotle in
which friendship is defined as the essential virtue, for instance.
Let me make just a single scholarly reference to Aristotle, who says that
there are three
types of friendship. Firstly, the higher friendship is
based on virtue and it has nothing to
do with politics. It is a
friendship between two virtuous men. Secondly, the friendship
grounded
on utility and usefulness, and this is political friendship. Third, and on
the lower
level, friendship grounded on pleasure - looking for pleasure
among young people,
Aristotle says. So you see that we have a concept
of friendship which is and is not
political. The political friendship
is one kind of friendship. One of the questions might be,
to put it in
a very everyday fashion, should we select our friends from among our political
allies, should we politically agree with a friend to enter into friendship,
is it necessary, are
politics and friendship homogeneous? Could we
have a friend who is politically an enemy
and vice versa, and so
forth? In Aristotle again you have this idea that the quest for justice
has nothing to do with politics, you have to go beyond or sometimes betray
friendship in
the name of justice. So, there are a number of problems
in which you see love - not
love, but philia or friendship playing an
organising role in the definition of the political
experience.
Then what I try to do - I'm looking at my watch - is to follow the thread of
the
paradoxes between friendship and politics, to look for a prevailing
canonical model of
friendship which in our culture form the Greeks to now,
in Greek culture, in Roman
culture, in Jewish, Christian and Islamic
culture, has been dominant, has been prevailing
and hegemonic. What
are the features of this prevailing hegemonic concept which could
be
politically meaningful and politically significant? I don't want to
homogenise of course
- this concept is not a single homogeneous concept, it
is not exactly the same in Greece,
in the Middle Ages, and today, but there
are some permanent features, and it is this set of
permanent features that I
try to discover, to analyse, to formalise from a political point of
view.
So, what are they? To be very, very, very rough: first of all the model
of this friendship is
a friendship between two young men, mortals, who have
a contract according to which
one will survive the other, one will be the
heir of the other, and they will agree politically
- I give a number of
examples of this. Which excludes first of all friendship between a
man
and a woman, or between women, so women are totally excluded from this model of
friendship: woman as the friend of a man or women as friends between
themselves. Then
the figure of the brother, of fraternity, is also at
the centre of this canonical model. I show
this of course through a
number of texts and examples. Brotherhood, fraternity, is the
figure
of this canonical friendship. Of course this concept of brotherhood has a
number of
cultural and historical premises. It comes from Greece, but
it also comes from the
Christian model in which brotherhood or fraternity is
essential. Men are all brothers
because they are sons of God, and you
can find the ethics of this concept in even an
apparently secular concept of
friendship and politics. In the French Revolution this is the
foundation of the Declaration of the Rights of Man. Fraternity was the
object of a terrible
debate in France at the time, and fraternity appears,
between equality and liberty, as one of
the foundations of the
republic. So, you have to deal here with what I would call a
phallocentric or phallogocentric concept of friendship. Which doesn't
of course mean to
me that the hegemony of this concept was so powerful that
what it excluded was
effectively totally excluded. It doesn't mean
that a woman couldn't have the experience of
friendship with a man or with
another woman. It means simply that within this culture,
this society,
by which this prevalent canon was considered legitimate, accredited, then
there was no voice, no discourse, no possibility of acknowledging these
excluded
possibilities.
So, all the concepts which are fundamental in politics - I just mentioned
those which
Geoff selected: sovereignty, power, representation - were
directly or indirectly marked
by this canonical concept. So, even the
idea of democracy, the way it was defined in the
beginning, had to agree
with the presuppositions of this concept, with the privilege
granted to man,
to brotherhood. What does brotherhood mean? It means of course the
family, the familial schema, filiation, it means brother instead of sister
and there are a
number of texts in which sister is simply a case of brother,
no different, and it makes no
difference. So, you have here all the
conditions for the canonical definition of politics, of
the state, the
relation to autochthony in Greece, to the territory, the nation-state,
filiation,
representation, sovereignty, all these share this phallocentric
concept of the social bond as
friendship. That's why I thought that
this leading thread, the problematic of friendship,
could be useful in order
to go on with the deconstruction of (let's say too quickly) the
massive bulk
of traditional political theory, and to provide me with a strategic lever to
continue the work I have done, while entering the field of politics in a
more efficient way.
3. What about democracy?
Now, the third question has to do with democracy: why the word 'democracy' in
'democracy to come', which I repeat again and again - because democracy is a
strange
name for a regime; from the beginning it was difficult to locate
democracy among the
spectrum of regimes, and everyone has always had
difficulty with assigning a place to
democracy. Democracy means,
minimally, equality - and here you see why friendship is
an important key,
because in friendship, even in classical friendship, what is involved is
reciprocity, equality, symmetry, and so on and so forth. There is no
democracy except as
equality among everyone - I'll try to make this everyone
more specific in a moment -
but an equality which can be calculated,
countable: you count the number of units, of
voters, of voices, of
citizens. On the other hand, you have to reconcile this demand for
equality with the demand for singularity, with respect for the Other as
singular, and that is
an aporia. How can we, at the same time, take
into account the equality of everyone,
justice and equity, and nevertheless
take into account and respect the heterogeneous
singularity of everyone?
From the beginning, democracy has been associated with values, with axioms,
which
belong to this canonical concept of friendship: that is brotherhood,
family, roots in a
territory (autochthony), the nation-state depending on a
territory, soil and place, and so
on. Now it is possible to think of a
democracy which could be, if not adjusted, then at
least articulated with
another concept of friendship, another experience of friendship which
wouldn't simply be dependent on or subordinate to what I call the prevalent
canonical
concept of friendship (phallogocentric, male, and so on and so
forth), and this is what I'm
trying to elaborate in the Politics of
Friendship. A democracy which is so strange that it
is no longer
simply reducible to citizenship, to the organisation of a regime for a given
society as nation-state. I've nothing simply against the nation-state,
I've tried to
understand what today goes beyond the borders of the
nation-state, and I'm now slowly
approaching the last question of
hospitality. What have been, what are and what will be
the limits of
the problematic of the nation-state? Is it possible that beyond the
nation-state
the concept of democracy keep not only a meaning but a force of
injunction? Can we
think of a democracy beyond the limits of the
classical political model, of the nation-state
and its borders? Is it
possible to think differently this double injunction of equality for
everyone and respect for singularity beyond the limits of classical politics
and classical
friendship?
It is in the name of this that we could try to question the canonical concept
of friendship.
Why would we do that in the first place, why are we
interested in questioning,
deconstructing if you want, the canonical concept
of friendship? It is in the name of
democracy. I think that
there is inequality and repression in the traditional concept of
friendship
such as we inherit it. It is in the name of more democracy that I think we
have
to unlock, to open, to displace this prevalent concept, and this is not
my initiative, not the
initiative of someone operating in a deconstructive
manner; it is what is happening today.
Today this model of brotherhood, man,
friendship is being deconstructed in the world.
What I say about the
nation-state is what is happening today in the world. This so-called
deconstruction is simply what is happening in a more or less visible way, in
an unequal
way with what is called the 'inequality of development'; because
today if you're interested
in this you can see how powerful the concept of
fraternity still is: in the rhetoric of
politicians, fraternity comes back
again and again, and sometimes it is very respectable,
but if you look for
the implications of this concept of fraternity you may have questions.
So when I speak of a 'democracy to come', I don't mean a future democracy, a
new
regime, a new organisation of nation-states (although this may be hoped
for) but I mean
this 'to come': the promise of an authentic democracy which
is never embodied in what we
call democracy. This is a way of going on
criticising what is everywhere given today
under the name of democracy in
our societies. This doesn't mean that 'democracy to
come' will be
simply a future democracy correcting or improving the actual conditions of
the so-called democracies, it means first of all that this democracy we
dream of is linked in
its concept to a promise. The idea of a promise
is inscribed in the idea of a democracy:
equality, freedom, freedom of
speech, freedom of the press - all these things are
inscribed as promises
within democracy. Democracy is a promise. That is why it is a
more historical concept of the political - it's the only concept of a regime
or a political
organisation in which history, that is the endless process of
improvement and perfectibility,
is inscribed in the concept. So, it's
a historical concept through and through, and that's
why I call it 'to
come': it is a promise and will remain a promise, but 'to come' means also
not a future but that it has 'to come' as a promise, as a duty, that is 'to
come' immediately.
We don't have to wait for future democracy to happen, to
appear, we have to do right
here and now what has to be done for it.
That's an injunction, an immediate injunction, no
delay. Which doesn't
mean that it will take the form of a regime; but if we dissociate
democracy
from the name of a regime we can then give this name 'democracy' to any kind
of experience in which there is equality, justice, equity, respect for the
singularity of the
Other at work, so to speak - then it's democracy here and
now; but of course this implies
that we do not confine democracy to the
political in the classical sense, or to the nation-
state, or to
citizenship.
We have today, for many reasons that we all know, to think of a democratic
relationship
not only with other citizens but also with non-citizens.
That's a modern experience; you
know that between the wars, after the first
World War, already there were in Europe -
Hannah Arendt paid special
attention to this - huge crowds of people not even in exile,
not even
deported but displaced persons who were not considered citizens, and, according
to Hannah Arendt, that is one of the origins of what happened in the second
World War.
This non-citizenship of people we have to care for, to welcome,
urges us, compels us, to
think of a democratic relationship beyond the
borders of the nation-state. That is the
invention of new practices,
new international law, the transformation of the sovereignty of
the
state. We all have examples of this situation today with what are called
non-
governmental interventions, everything which calls for interventions,
for political
initiatives, which should not depend on the sovereignty of the
state, that is, finally,
citizenship. In fact we know - that's why the
task is so enormous and endless - we
know today that even within
international organisations and institutions, the sovereignty of
the state
is a rule, and that in the name of international law some nation-states more
powerful than others make the law. Not only because this international
law is basically a
European law in the tradition of Europe and law, but
because these more powerful nation-
states make the law, that is they in
fact rule the international order. So, there are a number
of urgent
problems which require precisely this transformation of the concept of the
political, of the concept of democracy, and of the concept of
friendship. Now, this
accounts to some extent for the reasons I choose
the theme of hospitality as a privileged
theme in my recent seminars and
publications.
4. What about hospitality?
I have to - and that's an unconditional injunction - I have to welcome the
Other
whoever he or she is unconditionally, without asking for a document, a
name, a context,
or a passport. That is the very first opening of my
relation to the Other: to open my
space, my home - my house, my language, my
culture, my nation, my state, and myself.
I don't have to open it, because
it is open, it is open before I make a decision about it: then
I have to
keep it open or try to keep it open unconditionally. But of course this
unconditionality is a frightening thing, it's scary. If we decide
everyone will be able to
enter my space, my house, my home, my city, my
state, my language, and if we think what
I think, namely that this is
entering my space unconditionally may well be able to displace
everything in
my space, to upset, to undermine, to even destroy, then the worst may
happen
and I am open to this, the best and the worst. But of course since this
unconditional hospitality may lead to a perversion of this ethics of
friendship, we have to
condition this unconditionality, to negotiate the
relation between this unconditional
injunction and the necessary condition,
to organise this hospitality, which means laws,
rights, conventions, borders
of course, laws on immigration and so on and so forth. We
all have,
especially in Europe, on both sides of the channel, this problem of immigration,
to
what extent we should welcome the Other. So, in order to think of a
new politics of
hospitality, a new relationship to citizenship, to have to
re-think all these problems that I
have mentioned in the last few minutes.
Let me say just one more thing before I stop on this tradition of the concept
of hospitality,
given what I have said about citizenship and
non-citizenship. We could simply dream of a
democracy which would be
cosmopolitical, a cosmopolitan form. There is a tradition of
cosmopolitanism, and if we had time we could study this tradition, which
comes to us
from, on the one hand, Greek thought with the Stoics, who have a
concept of the 'citizen
of the world'. You also have St. Paul in the
Christian tradition, also a certain call for a
citizen of the world as,
precisely, a brother. St. Paul says that we are all brothers, that is
sons of God, so we are not foreigners, we belong to the world as citizens of
the world;
and it is this tradition that we could follow up until Kant for
instance, in whose concept of
cosmopolitanism we find the conditions for
hospitality. But in the concept of the
cosmopolitical in Kant there
are a number of conditions: first of all you should of course
welcome the
stranger, the foreigner, to the extent that he is a citizen of another country,
that you grant him the right to visit and not to stay, and there are a
number of other
conditions that I can't summarise here quickly, but this
concept of the cosmopolitical
which is very novel, very worthy of respect
(and I think cosmopolitanism is a very good
thing), is a very limited
concept. Limited precisely by the reference to the political, to the
state, to the authority of the state, to citizenship, and to strict control
of residency and
period of stay.
So, I think that what I try to call a 'New International' in Spectres of Marx
should go
beyond this concept of the cosmopolitical strictly speaking.
We have to do a lot of things,
and to work of course within the space of the
cosmopolitical, and an international law that
keeps alive the sovereignty of
the State. There is a lot to be done within the State and in
international organisations that respect the sovereignty of the State,
that's what we call
politics today, but beyond this task, which is enormous,
we must think and be oriented by
something which is more than
cosmopolitical, more than citizenship. So you see, just a
few
sentences before I stop, how strange is this itinerary calling for a new concept
of
democracy grounded - assuming this is a ground, and I'm not sure it is -
grounded on
this groundless experience of friendship, which shouldn't be
limited in the way it has been,
and a concept of democracy which would
re-define the political not only beyond the
nation-state but beyond the
cosmopolitical itself. That of course looks like a utopian or
very
distant perspective. I don't think so. Of course there is an
enormous distance if we
think that these things have to be reached and
concretely embodied, but we know today as
soon as we open a newspaper that
these problems are urgent and prevalent in everyday
life. In everyday
life we see that the classical concept of democracy, the way it inhabits all
the rhetoric of politicians and parliament, is shaken, that we need
something else. We see
that the concept of citizenship, the concept of
the border, immigration, are today under a
terrible seismic
displacement. We not only feel this: we can analyse this every day, so
what seems to be, and is, very far ahead of us, is also very close to us
every day, and it is
an urgent task to re-elaborate, to re-think, to
re-engage and to be committed differently
with these issues.
I see that my time's up, so I'll stop there.
Questions
Q1: On the notion of welcoming someone, of being hospitable to them:
well, firstly,
welcoming to what? To a thing, whatever that might
be? But secondly, it seems to me
that it implies a form of acceptance
and maybe inclusion, and I think that the notion of
inclusion is problematic
because it tends to imply some form of assimilation, and again
assimilating
someone to what? Which carries us on to the notion of equality, which can
be
coercive, and I wondered what you thought about the notion of coercion
and equality:
people aren't necessarily equal, nations aren't equal, states
aren't equal and what is the
form of agency that will make them equal and
therefore perhaps avoid assimilation?
J.D.: Thankyou. No, when I speak of hospitality I have in mind
the necessity not to
simply assimilate the Other, but that's an
aporia. We have to welcome the Other inside -
without that there would
be no hospitality, that the Other should be sheltered or welcomed
in my
space, that I should try to open my space, without trying to include the Other
in my
space. That is to ask that he or she learn my language, or adopt
my religion or become
English or become French, today for instance that's
the condition, that's the left-wing
discourse, the prevailing left-wing
discourse, 'we are hospitable to the immigrants to the
extent that they
become French citizens, respect secularism, that they learn the French
language', assimilation. We call this integration, and of course this
can be done in a novel
fashion and that is part of hospitality: if I want to
open my house of course my bed is your
bed, you want to use my bed? - it's
still a bed, you have to get used it; this is what I eat, I
can give you
what I eat; you have to get used to it. But that's a double bind, on the
one
hand I should respect the singularity of the Other and not to ask him or
her that he respect
or keep intact my own space or my own culture.
That's what I said at the beginning about the unconditionality. I have
to accept if I offer
unconditional hospitality that the Other may ruin my
own space or impose his or her own
culture or his or her own language.
That's the problem: hospitality should be neither
assimilation,
acculturation, nor simply the occupation of my space by the Other. That's
why it has to be negotiated at every instant, and the decision for
hospitality, the best rule
for this negotiation, has to be invented at every
second with all the risks involved, and it is
very risky. Hospitality,
and hospitality is a very general name for all our relations to the
Other,
has to be re-invented at every second, it is something without a pre-given rule.
That is what we have to invent - a new language for instance. When two
people who
don't speak the same language meet, what should they do?
They have to translate, but
translation is an invention, to invent a new way
of translating in which translation doesn't
simply go one way but both ways,
and how can we do that? That's the aporia, and this is
political, the
new form - but it had always been a form - of politics, but today it has,
because of the development of communication, of crossing borders, of
telecommunications, it has new forms of urgency.
Q2: What in a sense I found missing from your talk is an explanation
of why borders,
sovereignty, the old structures of politics, are being
transformed. You don't seem to be
able to name the process through
which this is happening, and it seems to me that one
could understand what
you're talking about in terms of globalisation, the formation of a
common
social space, a single world-meaning within which all these old structures which
try to absolutise and fix differences are changed, but this, it also seems
to me, is a ground
on which to found a new form of democracy, and that
ground has to be found in the
concept of globality and in the concept of
world unification. I wonder what your response
is to this?
J.D.: Everything I have said up to now was referring to what you
called 'globalisation',
what we call in French 'mondialisation'.
That's the only thing I've said; but why didn't I
use the name
'globalisation'? Because today it's a confused concept and it's the screen
for
a number of non-concepts and sometimes of political tricks and political
strategies. Of
course something like globalisation is happening - not
only today of course, it started a
long time ago - but today there is an
acceleration of this mondialisation, but as you
know, using this word, this
key word, allows a number of political appropriations - in the
name of the
free market for instance. People try to have us swallow the idea that
globalisation means the free market, or that the concentration of
tele-technological
communications beyond the States are what makes
globalisation possible, and what should
be supported or simply
accepted. So I have, and I'm not the only one, many, many,
reservations about the use one makes of this word: but I agree with you,
this is, if not the
ground (because I don't think it is a ground), but this
is the space in which these problems
take their shape. I agree with
you, but I wouldn't simply rely upon the word 'globalisation'
in order to
name this phenomenon.
Q3: This is a question about the book, if I could begin with the
second essay and perhaps
go on to the first. When you speak about the
'voice of the friend' in Being and Time you
say it could be subjected to a
certain kind of deconstructive critique that perhaps Husserl
might have
called for, and then you ask: why does this phrase appear in Heidegger?
Why
not construe it in an obvious way as a reference to Aristotle's
discussion of friendship in
The Ethics, and indeed to book one of The
Nicomachean Ethics, to which Heidegger does
refer in earlier discussion in
courses from which that section of Being and Time is drawn?
The point of
that would be that it looks like Heidegger thinks that there might be a more
interesting account or perception of friendship in Aristotle, and one which
could go
beyond a certain kind of critique that we would perhaps find in the
first text of the book,
and indeed if you read The Nicomachean Ethics it
does seem that Aristotle has this worry
and this conflict between
universality and singularity in friendship, and this problem of
nearness and
distance, and that to engage in virtue, true friendship, one would have to like
the friend for their sake and not for one's own sake; and this seems to call
for a certain
separation - and so when he gives examples of true friendship
the examples will be of
women separated from their children and people
separated by political enmity, enemies in
war who nevertheless remain within
this true friendship. The question is: isn't there in
Aristotle, and
indeed throughout the history of the so called reflection on friendship, a
worry that somewhere anticipates what you have called the non-canonical view
of
friendship? And doesn't the non-canonical, and perhaps Kantian view
- in that it seems
that in the notion of respect Kant introduces, he make
explicit a worry that will have been
there going back to Aristotle - doesn't
the non-canonical inhabit the canonical?
J.D.: Thankyou. This is a very rich intervention and a difficult
question, especially all the
more difficult because you have read this
chapter in French because it's not included in the
English version!
[Laughter]. Let me tell everyone by the way that the English version is
the book Politics of Friendship without an essay which comes at the end, to
which you've
just referred, in an appendix and which can be read in French
in Politiques de l'amitié or in
English - it has been published in the
United States. So, it's a very difficult question. It
has to do
with Heidegger's mention in Being and Timeof the voice of the friend we have in
us. It's a very strange occurrence, because suddenly, in a context in
which no one would
expect the friend to appear there is this reference which
puzzles every reader of
Heidegger. So I tried in this chapter to
account for this single reference to the voice of the
friend in us, but I
can't re-constitute what I do in this chapter, which is to try to
reconstitute the politics of friendship in Heidegger and the way in other
text he thematises
friendship, loss, war, peace, the polemos, the political,
and so on and so forth. To answer
very briefly your difficult question
I would say that in the context of Being and Time it is
difficult to speak
of a politics of friendship on a political level in this context. I think
that
the friend he is referring to cannot be identified with anything
Aristotle has to tell you,
there is no reference to virtue, even less to
utility or to pleasure. So although Heidegger
of course knew these
texts by Aristotle I don't think that there is even an indirect reference
to
Aristotle, I don't think so but I cannot demonstrate this here, you think so?
Q3: But it's a quotation from book one of The Nichomachean Ethics.
J.D.: Perhaps, in which case I missed a quotation and please give me
the reference. I'm
ready to consider this, if it's a hidden quotation
this could account for the strangeness of
this reference. As if
Heidegger was saying 'well everyone knows what Aristotle said and
that's the
friend I am referring to.'
Q4: I admire your injunction to teaching symbology and looking for new
modes of
friendship and communication but I was struck, unless I've made a
mistake, by the quite
positivistic character of friendship: you say it
cannot be completely described theoretically,
it has to be approached and
accepted, and that reminded me ...
J.D.: 'Approached and...'?
Q4: Accepted.
J.D.: I didn't say accepted.
Q4: You said you cannot theorise friendship, so it seems positivitic.
J.D.: No, when I say you can't theorise it that is not
positivistic. I mean of course we can
theorise, that is what I do!
[Laughter]. I try to do that, but I argue that there is something
which has to be theoretically determined as going beyond theory - but that's
not
positivist.
Q4: I was interested also in the metaphor of translation across
culture which you used,
and I think there is also quite an interesting
parallel to be drawn about what we might call
trans-historical
communication, whereas translation would be trans-cultural through
language
...
J.D.: Let's say trans-.
Q4: The transhistorical or the history of ideas is an interesting
element of what you
brought out, so I congratulate you [laughter].
J.D.: That's the hospitality I love, that's hospitality the way I understand it!
Q5: On the cover of the book Politics of Friendship it says 'At issue
is an anti-genealogy
upsetting the genealogical motif itself'. Does
this book mark a move away from
Nietzsche?
J.D.: Yes, in fact it's perhaps one of the first times - I try in this
context to disassociate
gestures that I have already constantly associated
before now, that is deconstruction and
genealogy. Deconstruction as
being at least partly a genealogical anamnesis or
deconstitution of a series
of traditional layers, a deconstitutive genealogy in a Nietzschean
sense. To that extent deconstruction was tied to a certain Nietzschean
concept of
genealogy, but in this context, for the reasons I gave earlier
(that is the fact that the
classical concept of democracy, the political,
brotherhood, fraternity was genealogical,
that is grounded on filiation,
family, autochthony, the territory) I thought that I should
suspect the
authority of genealogy at some point from that point of view. That is to
disassociate the deconstruction of the concept of fraternity from the
genealogical scheme
or to think of another kind of genealogy. There is
still genealogy, but it's a genealogy that
goes in the opposite direction,
it's a way of questioning the unquestioned authority of
genealogy. I'm
not against genealogy or simply for it, but I want to be more careful about
its implications.
Q6: You talk about geographical exclusion and how your idea of
hospitality can address
that, but you haven't mentioned the way in which
geographical exclusion is completely tied
up with economic exclusion.
The countries from which it's difficult to get into England
are poor
countries: it's not really France or Germany, it's the Caribbean, it's Africa,
it's the
Indian sub-continent, and I wondered how you think your concept of
friendship, your non-
canonical concept of friendship, can address economic
exclusion, and especially economic
exclusion in its most extreme form which
is the exclusion by those who own capital of
everyone else. You can't
ask those who own capital to be hospitable ...
J.D.: I ask them nevertheless [laughter].
Q6: It's naive to ask them, it's a naive request.
J.D.: Perhaps, but I still do. The problem of the economy,
although I didn't refer to it
explicitly in this short presentation, is at
the centre of this. It's a problem of economy, of
appropriation,
misappropriation, hospitality is economy. This is the question we
addressed a moment ago about assimilation, which means appropriation, that
is
exploitation, and so on and so forth. So, I think of course that
the problem of capitalism is
at the centre of this question; if I didn't
name it before I apologise, but it is at the centre of
this attempt, without
a doubt. When I try to question or to deconstruct the classical
concept of the political, it is in order to open it on to other fields,
spaces, strata and layers,
such as the economical or economy in the broad
sense. In the narrow sense of use and
exchange values, capital,
speculation, financial return and also in the broader sense of
propriety,
the proper, what is proper to whom, appropriation, and the concept of
hospitality should not remain outside of this, and of who owns what.
It consists of
opening your own space, your own goods, your own house and
nation, it's economical
and it has to do with economy; and of course however
naive I may be, I'm not totally
unaware of the problems of the poor being
more excluded at the border than the rich. In
my own country I can see
this every day, at the airport I see who enters easily and who
does not with
the same legislation. Thankyou for your suggestion, but I'm not totally
blind to these questions.
Q6: I am only saying: how can you use your concept of hospitality to
address the problem
of capitalism?
J.D.: I can't do it right here and now, but I think this is the
problem, the problem that has
to be faced no doubt. What I call the
transformation of international law implies a
transformation of the market,
of the global market, and you can't touch the global market
without touching
capitalism. Everything I say here has to do with that, it would have been
easier for me to say 'Well, that's capitalism', but capitalism is precisely
tied to this
organisation of the political, the classical organisation of
the political. At the same time I
think it's a little more complex
than that, and I think that the development of new forms of
capitalism are
responsible for, on the one hand the consolidation of the old concepts of
politics, democracy, friendship, etc., but at the same time undermining this
tradition. It's
because of new developments of capitalism that
everything is shaken. When you see that
for instance the concentration
of the powers of the media and tele-technologies goes
beyond state power,
becomes international, on the one hand it confirms the traditional
structures of politics, and on the other it deconstructs them. There
is a deconstructing
effect of capitalism, that's why the approach to
capitalism is very complex, but I agree
with you it's a central problem.
Q7: I wanted to link into this last question, and I just wanted to ask
you if you think it's
possible to transform a concept like democracy without
linking that attempt to an attempt
to transform material reality? In
other words, the example you used about immigration
and democracy - the fact
that under bourgeois democracy in theory everyone is free to
go wherever
they like and do whatever they like, except if you're seen as the wrong colour
you can't cross the border, or if you don't fit with the politics of a
certain nation - and
doesn't that mean that basically we have to go back to
Marx and say that to throw your
weight behind the struggle of the exploited
against the exploiters is the only way you can
go beyond the limits of
bourgeois democracy? Don't we have to go beyond discourse and
look to
a systematic attempt to change the world?
J.D.: We won't change the world before two o'clock [laughter], but
what I'm saying is that
we have to, and through the transformation of the
organisation of capitalism, to a
transformation of the Marxist heritage,
taking into account what's happening today
especially in terms of
citizenship and colour of skin and so on and so forth; and when I'm
not
giving a lecture at the University of Sussex I try to do my best as a French
citizen to
fight for the transformation of the laws on immigration in my
country, which is a very
burning issue right now in the French
parliament. I'll do what I can to intervene, very
modestly and
minimally, in this field of concrete and urgent questions. We have to do
both, to speak and to act.
Q8: I actually wanted to address one of your other books in relation
to what you have
been saying today when you talk about a visitor coming into
your country, and sharing,
and also the necessity to break down capitalism,
and I'm just wondering - since this is
about relations between different
individuals, different citizens, different nation-states -
about going back
to The Other Heading and re-thinking yourself and re-thinking what
happens. Do you think that in some ways because there is this
interplay of the Other and
yourself in friendship that you are in some ways
the Other and that the Other is in you?
J.D.: Yes, it complicates the issue, because the Other is not simply
the Other as coming
from the outside so to speak. One is the one, I am
the one, one is more or less the one
and everyone is more or less the one
and more or less one with him or herself. Which
means that the Other
is already inside, and has to be sheltered and welcomed in a certain
way. We have to negotiate also, that's a complicated unconscious
operation, to negotiate
the hospitality within ourselves. To this one
in ourselves, to this image that might exclude
this other one or be allergic
to this other one. We know that someone who doesn't
negotiate this
hospitality in him or herself in a certain way cannot be hospitable to the
Other, that's what the Greeks taught us. That you have to solve the
problem within
yourself, and it's already a society, a multiplicity of
heterogeneous singularities, to be
really smiling to the Other. If you
are at war with yourself you may be allergic to the
Other, that's what
complicates the issue.