Chapter 4
Of the Divine Law
The word law, taken in the abstract, means that by which an individual, or all
things, or as many things as belong to a particular species, act in one and the
same fixed and definite manner, which manner depends either on natural necessity
or on human decree. A law which depends on natural necessity is one which
necessarily follows from the nature, or from the definition of the thing in
question; a law which depends on human decree, and which is more
correctly called an ordinance, is one which men have laid down for themselves
and others in order to live more safely or conveniently, or from some similar
reason.
For example, the law that all bodies impinging on lesser bodies, lose as
much of their own motion as they communicate to the latter is a universal law of all bodies, and depends on natural
necessity. So, too, the law that a man in remembering one thing, straightway
remembers another either like it, or which he had perceived simultaneously with
it, is a law which necessarily follows from the nature of man. But the law that men must yield, or be compelled to yield,
somewhat of their natural right, and that they bind themselves to live in
a certain way, depends on human decree. Now, though I freely admit that all
things are predetermined by universal natural laws to exist and operate in a given, fixed, and
definite manner, I still assert that the laws I have just mentioned depend on human decree.
(1.) Because man, in so far as he is a part of nature,
constitutes a part of the power of nature. Whatever, therefore, follows
necessarily from the necessity of human nature (that is, from nature herself, in
so far as we conceive of her as acting through man) follows, even though it be
necessarily, from human power. Hence the sanction of such laws may very well be said to depend on man's decree,
for it principally depends on the power of the human mind; so that the human mind in respect to its perception of things as
true and false, can readily be conceived as without such laws, but not without
necessary law as we have just defined it.
(2.) I have stated that these laws depend on human decree because it is well to
define and explain things by their proximate causes. The general consideration
of fate and the concatenation of causes would aid us very little in forming and
arranging our ideas concerning particular questions. Let us add that as to the
actual coordination and concatenation of things, that is how things are ordained
and linked together, we are obviously ignorant; therefore, it is more profitable
for right living, nay, it is necessary for us to consider things as contingent. So much about law in the abstract.
Now the word law seems to be only applied to natural phenomena by
analogy, and is commonly taken to signify a command which men can either obey or
neglect, inasmuch as it restrains human nature within certain originally
exceeded limits, and therefore lays down no rule beyond human strength. Thus it
is expedient to define law more particularly as a plan of life laid down by
man for himself or others with a certain object.
However, as the true object of legislation is only
perceived by a few, and most men are almost incapable of grasping it, though
they live under its conditions, legislators, with a view to exacting general
obedience, have wisely put forward another object, very different from that
which necessarily follows from the nature of law: they promise to the observers
of the law that which the masses chiefly desire, and threaten its violators with
that which they chiefly fear: thus endeavouring to restrain the masses, as far
as may be, like a horse with a curb; whence it follows that the word law is chiefly applied to the modes of life enjoined on
men by the sway of others; hence those who obey the law are said to live under
it and to be under compulsion. In truth, a man who renders everyone their due
because he fears the gallows, acts under the sway and compulsion of others, and
cannot be called just. But a man who does the same from a knowledge of the true
reason for laws and their necessity, acts from a firm purpose and of his own
accord, and is therefore properly called just. This, I take it, is Paul's
meaning when he says, that those who live under the law cannot be justified through the law, for justice,
as commonly defined, is the constant and perpetual will to render every man his
due. Thus Solomon says (Prov. xxi:15), "It is a joy to the just
to do judgment," but the wicked fear.
Law, then, being a plan of living which men have for a
certain object laid down for themselves or others, may, as it seems, be divided
into human law and Divine law.
By human law I mean a plan of living which serves only to
render life and the state secure.
By Divine law I mean that which only regards the highest good, in other words, the true knowledge of God
and love.
I call this law Divine because of the nature of the highest good, which I will here shortly explain as
clearly as I can.
Inasmuch as the intellect is the best part of our being, it is evident
that we should make every effort to perfect it as far as possible if we desire
to search for what is really profitable to us. For in intellectual perfection the highest good should consist. Now, since all our
knowledge, and the certainty which removes every doubt, depend solely on the
knowledge of God;- firstly, because without God nothing can exist or be
conceived; secondly, because so long as we have no clear and distinct idea of
God we may remain in universal doubt - it follows that our highest good and perfection also depend solely on the
knowledge of God. Further, since without God nothing can exist or be conceived,
it is evident that all natural phenomena involve and express the conception of
God as far as their essence and perfection extend, so that we have greater
and more perfect knowledge of God in proportion to our knowledge of natural
phenomena: conversely (since the knowledge of an effect through its cause is the
same thing as the knowledge of a particular property of a cause) the greater our
knowledge of natural phenomena, the more perfect is our knowledge of the essence of God (which is the cause of all things). So,
then, our highest good not only depends on the knowledge of God,
but wholly consists therein; and it further follows that man is perfect or the
reverse in proportion to the nature and perfection of the object of his special
desire; hence the most perfect and the chief sharer in the highest blessedness is he who prizes above all else, and takes
especial delight in, the intellectual knowledge of God, the most perfect Being.
Hither, then, our highest good and our highest blessedness aim - namely, to the knowledge and love of
God; therefore the means demanded by this aim of all human actions, that is, by
God in so far as the idea of him is in us, may be called the commands of God,
because they proceed, as it were, from God Himself, inasmuch as He exists in our
minds, and the plan of life which has regard to this aim may be fitly called the
law of God.
The nature of the means, and the plan of life which
this aim demands, how the foundations of the best states follow its lines, and how men's life is
conducted, are questions pertaining to general ethics. Here I only proceed to
treat of the Divine law in a particular application.
As the love of God is man's highest happiness and blessedness, and the ultimate end and aim of all human
actions, it follows that he alone lives by the Divine law who loves God not from fear of punishment,
or from love of any other object, such as sensual pleasure, fame, or the like;
but solely because he has knowledge of God, or is convinced that the knowledge
and love of God is the highest good. The sum and chief precept, then, of the
Divine law is to love God as the highest good, namely, as we have said, not from fear of
any pains and penalties, or from the love of any other object in which we desire
to take pleasure. The idea of God lays down the rule that God is our highest good - in other words, that the knowledge and
love of God is the ultimate aim to which all our actions should be directed. The
worldling cannot understand these things, they appear foolishness to him because
he has too meager a knowledge of God, and also because in this highest good he can discover nothing which he can
handle or eat, or which affects the fleshly appetites wherein he chiefly
delights, for it consists solely in thought and the pure reason. They, on the other hand, who know that they
possess no greater gift than intellect and sound reason, will doubtless accept what I have said without
question.
We have now explained that wherein the Divine law chiefly consists, and what are human laws, namely, all those which have a different
aim unless they have been ratified by revelation, for in this respect also things are
referred to God (as we have shown above) and in this sense the law of Moses, although it was not universal, but entirely
adapted to the disposition and particular preservation of a single people, may
yet be called a law of God or Divine law, inasmuch as we believe that it was ratified
by prophetic insight. If we consider the nature of natural Divine law as we have just explained it, we shall see:
I. That it is universal or common to all men, for we have deduced it
from universal human nature.
II. That it does not
depend on the truth of any historical narrative whatsoever, for inasmuch as this
natural Divine law is comprehended solely by the consideration
of human nature, it is plain that we can conceive it as existing as well in Adam
as in any other man, as well in a man living among his fellows, as in a man who
lives by himself.
The truth of a historical narrative, however assured,
cannot give us the knowledge nor consequently the love of God, for love of God
springs from knowledge of Him, and knowledge of Him should be derived from
general ideas, in themselves certain and known, so that the truth of a
historical narrative is very far from being a necessary requisite for our
attaining our highest good.
Still, though the truth of histories cannot give us
the knowledge and love of God, I do not deny that reading them is very useful
with a view to life in the world, for the more we have observed and known of
men's customs and circumstances, which are best revealed by their actions, the
more warily we shall be able to order our lives among them, and so far as reason dictates to adapt our actions to their
dispositions.
III. We see that this natural Divine law does not demand the performance of
ceremonies - that is, actions in themselves indifferent, which are called good
from the fact of their institution, or actions symbolizing something profitable
for salvation, or (if one prefers this definition) actions of which the meaning
surpasses human understanding. The natural light of reason does not demand anything which it is itself
unable to supply, but only such as it can very clearly show to be good, or a
means to our blessedness. Such things as are good simply because
they have been commanded or instituted, or as being symbols of something good,
are mere shadows which cannot be reckoned among actions that are the offspring
as it were, or fruit of a sound mind and of intellect. There is no need for me to go into this now
in more detail.
IV. Lastly, we see that the highest reward of the Divine law is the law itself, namely, to know God and
to love Him of our free choice, and with an undivided and fruitful spirit; while
its penalty is the absence of these things, and being in bondage to the flesh -
that is, having an inconstant and wavering spirit.
These points being noted, I must now inquire:
I. Whether by the natural light of reason we can conceive of God as a law-giver or
potentate ordaining laws for men?
II. What is the
teaching of Holy Writ concerning this natural light of reason and natural law?
III.
With what objects were ceremonies formerly instituted?
IV. Lastly, what is the good gained by knowing the
sacred histories and believing them?
Of the first two I will treat
in this chapter, of the remaining two in the following one.
Our conclusion about the first is easily deduced from
the nature of God's will, which is only distinguished from His understanding in relation to our intellect - that is, the will and the understanding of God are in reality one and the same,
and are only distinguished in relation to our thoughts which we form concerning
God's understanding. For instance, if we are only looking to the fact that the
nature of a triangle is from eternity contained in the Divine nature as an eternal verity, we say that God possesses the idea of a
triangle, or that He understands the nature of a triangle; but if afterwards we
look to the fact that the nature of a triangle is thus contained in the Divine
nature, solely by the necessity of the Divine nature, and not by the necessity
of the nature and essence of a triangle - in fact, that the necessity of a
triangle's essence and nature, in so far as they are conceived of as eternal verities, depends solely on the necessity of
the Divine nature and intellect, we then style God's will or decree, that
which before we styled His intellect. Wherefore we make one and the same affirmation concerning God when we say that He has from
eternity decreed that three angles of a triangle are
equal to two right angles, as when we say that He has understood it.
Hence the affirmations and the negations of God always involve necessity or truth; so
that, for example, if God said to Adam that He did not wish him to eat of the
tree of knowledge of good and evil, it would have involved a contradiction that
Adam should have been able to eat of it, and would therefore have been
impossible that he should have so eaten, for the Divine command would have
involved an eternal necessity and truth. But since Scripture
nevertheless narrates that God did give this command to Adam, and yet that none
the less Adam ate of the tree, we must perforce say that God revealed to Adam
the evil which would surely follow if he should eat of the tree, but did not
disclose that such evil would of necessity come to pass. Thus it was that Adam
took the revelation to be not an eternal and necessary truth, but a law - that is, an ordinance followed by gain or loss,
not depending necessarily on the nature of the act performed, but solely on the
will and absolute power of some potentate, so that the revelation in question was solely in relation to Adam,
and solely through his lack of knowledge a law, and God was, as it were, a
lawgiver and potentate. From the same cause, namely, from lack of knowledge, the
Decalogue in relation to the Hebrews was a law, for since they knew not the existence of God as an eternal truth, they must have taken as a law that which
was revealed to them in the Decalogue, namely, that God exists, and that God
only should be worshipped. But if God had spoken to them without the
intervention of any bodily means, immediately they would have perceived it not
as a law, but as an eternal truth.
What we have said about the Israelites and Adam,
applies also to all the prophets who wrote laws in God's name - they did not
adequately conceive God's decrees as eternal truths. For instance, we must say of Moses that from revelation, from the basis of what was revealed to him,
he perceived the method by which the Israelitish nation could best be united in
a particular territory, and could form a body politic or state, and further that he perceived the method by
which that nation could best be constrained to obedience; but he did not
perceive, nor was it revealed to him, that this method was absolutely the best,
nor that the obedience of the people in a certain strip of territory would
necessarily imply the end he had in view. Wherefore he perceived these things
not as eternal truths, but as precepts and ordinances, and he
ordained them as laws of God, and thus it came to be that he conceived God as a
ruler, a legislator, a king, as merciful, just, &c., whereas such qualities
are simply attributes of human nature, and utterly alien from the nature of the
Deity. Thus much we may affirm of the prophets who wrote laws in the name of
God; but we must not affirm it of Christ, for Christ, although He too seems to have
written laws in the name of God, must be taken to have had a clear and adequate
perception, for Christ was not so much a prophet as the mouthpiece of
God. For God made revelations to mankind through Christ as He had before done through angels - that is,
a created voice, visions, &c. It would be as unreasonable to say that God
had accommodated his revelations to the opinions of Christ as that He had before accommodated them to the
opinions of angels (that is, of a created voice or visions) as matters to be
revealed to the prophets, a wholly absurd hypothesis. Moreover, Christ was sent to teach not only the Jews but the
whole human race, and therefore it was not enough that His mind should be
accommodated to the opinions the Jews alone, but also to the opinion and
fundamental teaching common to the whole human race - in other words, to ideas universal and true. Inasmuch as God revealed
Himself to Christ, or to Christ's mind immediately, and not as to
the prophets through words and symbols, we must needs suppose that Christ perceived truly what was revealed, in other
words, He understood it, for a matter is understood when it is perceived simply by the mind
without words or symbols.
Christ, then, perceived (truly and adequately) what was
revealed, and if He ever proclaimed such revelations as laws, He did so because of the ignorance
and obstinacy of the people, acting in this respect the part of God; inasmuch as
He accommodated Himself to the comprehension of the people, and though He spoke
somewhat more clearly than the other prophets, yet He taught what was revealed
obscurely, and generally through parables, especially when He was speaking to
those to whom it was not yet given to understand the kingdom of heaven. (See
Matt. xiii:10, &c.) To those to whom it was given to understand the
mysteries of heaven, He doubtless taught His doctrines as eternal truths, and did not lay them down as laws, thus
freeing the minds of His hearers from the bondage of that law which He further
confirmed and established. Paul apparently points to this more than once (e.g.
Rom. vii:6, and iii:28), though he never himself seems to wish to speak openly,
but, to quote his own words (Rom. iii:6, and vi:19), "merely humanly." This he
expressly states when he calls God just, and it was doubtless in concession to
human weakness that he attributes mercy, grace, anger, and similar qualities to
God, adapting his language to the popular mind, or, as he puts it (1 Cor. iii:1,
2), to carnal men. In Rom. ix:18, he teaches undisguisedly that God's auger and
mercy depend not on the actions of men, but on God's own nature or will;
further, that no one is justified by the works of the law, but only by faith,
which he seems to identify with the full assent of the soul; lastly, that no one
is blessed unless he have in him the mind of Christ (Rom. viii:9), whereby he perceives the laws of
God as eternal truths. We conclude, therefore, that God is
described as a lawgiver or prince, and styled just, merciful, &c., merely in
concession to popular understanding, and the imperfection of popular knowledge;
that in reality God acts and directs all things simply by the necessity of His
nature and perfection, and that His decrees and volitions are eternal truths, and always involve necessity. So much
for the first point which I wished to explain and demonstrate.
Passing on to the second point, let us search the
sacred pages for their teaching concerning the light of nature and this Divine law. The first doctrine we find in the history
of the first man, where it is narrated that God commanded Adam not to eat of the
fruit of the tree of the knowledge of good and evil; this seems to mean that God
commanded Adam to do and to seek after righteousness because it was good, not
because the contrary was evil: that is, to seek the good for its own sake, not
from fear of evil. We have seen that he who acts rightly from the true knowledge
and love of right, acts with freedom and constancy, whereas he who acts from
fear of evil, is under the constraint of evil, and acts in bondage under
external control. So that this commandment of God to Adam comprehends the whole
Divine natural law, and absolutely agrees with the dictates of the light of
nature; nay, it would be easy to explain on this basis the whole history or
allegory of the first man. But I prefer to pass over the subject in silence,
because, in the first place, I cannot be absolutely certain that my explanation
would be in accordance with the intention of the sacred writer; and, secondly,
because many do not admit that this history is an allegory, maintaining it to be
a simple narrative of facts. It will be better, therefore, to adduce other
passages of Scripture, especially such as were written by him, who speaks with
all the strength of his natural understanding, in which he surpassed all his
contemporaries, and whose sayings are accepted by the people as of equal weight
with those of the prophets. I mean Solomon, whose prudence and wisdom are commended in
Scripture rather than his piety and gift of prophecy. He, in his proverbs calls the human intellect
the well-spring of true life, and declares that misfortune is made up of folly.
"Understanding is a well-spring of life to him that hath it; but the instruction
of fools is folly," Prov. xvi. 22. Life being taken to mean the true life (as is
evident from Deut. xxx. 19), the fruit of the understanding consists only in the true life, and its
absence constitutes punishment. All this absolutely agrees with what was set out
in our fourth point concerning natural law. Moreover our position that it is the
well-spring of life, and that the intellect alone lays down laws for the wise, is plainly
taught by, the sage, for he says (Prov. xiii. 14): "The law of the wise is a
fountain of life " - that is, as we gather from the preceding text, the understanding. In chap. iii. 13, he expressly teaches
that the understanding renders man blessed and happy, and gives
him true peace of mind. "Happy is the man that findeth wisdom, and the man that
getteth understanding," for "Wisdom gives length of days, and
riches and honour; her ways are ways of pleasantness, and all her paths peace"
(iii 16, 17). According to Solomon, therefore, it is only, the wise who live in
peace and equanimity, not like the wicked whose minds drift hither and thither,
and (as Isaiah says, chap. lvii:20) "are like the troubled sea, for them there
is no peace."
Lastly, we should especially note the passage in chap.
ii. of Solomon's proverbs which most clearly confirms our
contention: "If thou criest after knowledge, and liftest up thy voice for understanding . . . then shalt thou understand the fear
of the Lord, and find the knowledge of God; for the Lord giveth wisdom; out of
His mouth cometh knowledge and understanding." These words clearly enunciate, that
wisdom or intellect alone teaches us to fear God wisely - that
is, to worship Him truly;, that wisdom and knowledge flow from God's mouth, and
that God bestows on us this gift; this we have already shown in proving that our
understanding and our knowledge depend on, spring from,
and are perfected by the idea or knowledge of God, and nothing else. Solomon goes on to say in so many words that this
knowledge contains and involves the true principles of ethics and politics:
"When wisdom entereth into thy heart, and knowledge is pleasant to thy soul,
discretion shall preserve thee, understanding shall keep thee, then shalt thou
understand righteousness, and judgment, and equity, yea every good path." All of
which is in obvious agreement with natural knowledge: for after we have come to
the understanding of things, and have tasted the excellence
of knowledge, she teaches us ethics and true virtue.
Thus the happiness and the peace of him who cultivates
his natural understanding lies, according to Solomon also, not so much under the dominion of fortune
(or God's external aid) as in inward personal virtue (or God's internal aid),
for the latter can to a great extent be preserved by vigilance, right action,
and thought.
Lastly, we must by no means pass over the passage in
Paul's Epistle to the Romans, i:20, in which he says: "For the invisible things
of God from the creation of the world are clearly seen, being understood by the
things that are made, even His eternal power and Godhead; so that they are without
excuse, because, when they knew God, they glorified Him not as God, neither were
they thankful." These words clearly show that everyone can by the light of
nature clearly understand the goodness and the eternal divinity of God, and can thence know and deduce
what they should seek for and what avoid; wherefore the Apostle says that they
are without excuse and cannot plead ignorance, as they certainly might if it
were a question of supernatural light and the incarnation, passion, and resurrection of Christ. "Wherefore," he goes on to say (ib. 24), "God
gave them up to uncleanness through the lusts of their own hearts;" and so on,
through the rest of the chapter, he describes the vices of ignorance, and sets
them forth as the punishment of ignorance. This obviously agrees with the verse
of Solomon, already quoted, "The instruction of fools is
folly," so that it is easy to understand why Paul says that the wicked are
without excuse. As every man sows so shall he reap: out of evil, evils
necessarily spring, unless they be wisely counteracted.
Thus we see that Scripture literally approves of the light of natural reason and the natural Divine law, and I have fulfilled the promises made at the beginning of this chapter.