Chapter 15
Philosophy Is Shown Not To Be Subservient to Theology: A Definition of Reason Which Enables Us To Accept the Authority of the Bible
Those who know not that theology and reason are distinct, dispute whether Scripture should
be made subservient to reason, or reason to Scripture: that is, whether the
meaning of Scripture should be made to agreed with reason; or whether reason should be made to agree with
Scripture: the latter position is assumed by the sceptics who deny the certitude
of reason, the former by the dogmatists. Both parties are, as I have shown,
utterly in the wrong, for either doctrine would require us to tamper with reason
or with Scripture.
We have shown that Scripture does not teach philosophy, but merely obedience, and that all it
contains has been adapted to the understanding and established opinions of the
multitude. Those, therefore, who wish to adapt it to philosophy, must needs
ascribe to the prophets many ideas which they never even dreamed of, and give an
extremely forced interpretation to their words: those on the other hand, who
would make reason and philosophy subservient to theology, will be forced to accept as Divine utterances
the prejudices of the ancient Jews, and to fill and confuse their mind
therewith. In short, one party will run wild with the aid of reason, and the other will run wild without the aid of
reason.
The first among the Pharisees who openly maintained
that Scripture should be made to agree with reason, was Maimonides, whose opinion we reviewed, and abundantly
refuted in Chap. 8.: now, although this writer had much authority among his
contemporaries, he was deserted on this question by almost all, and the majority
went straight over to the opinion of a certain R. Jehuda Alpakhar, who, in his
anxiety to avoid the error of Maimonides, fell into another, which was its exact
contrary. He held that reason should be made subservient, and entirely give way
to Scripture. He thought that a passage should not be interpreted
metaphorically, simply because it was repugnant to reason, but only in the cases
when it is inconsistent with Scripture itself - that is, with its clear
doctrines. Therefore he laid down the universal rule, that whatsoever Scripture
teaches dogmatically, and affirms expressly, must on its own sole authority be
admitted as absolutely true: that there is no doctrine in the Bible which
directly contradicts the general tenour of the whole: but only some which appear
to involve a difference, for the phrases of Scripture often seem to imply
something contrary to what has been expressly taught. Such phrases, and such
phrases only, we may interpret metaphorically.
For instance, Scripture clearly teaches the unity of
God (see Deut. vi:4), nor is there any text distinctly asserting a plurality of
gods; but in several passages God speaks of Himself, and the prophets speak of
Him, in the plural number; such phrases are simply a manner of speaking, and do
not mean that there actually are several gods: they are to be explained
metaphorically, not because a plurality of gods is repugnant to reason, but
because Scripture distinctly asserts that there is only one.
So, again, as Scripture asserts (as Alpakhar thinks)
in Deut. iv:15, that God is incorporeal, we are bound, solely by the authority
of this text, and not by reason, to believe that God has no body: consequently
we must explain metaphorically, on the sole authority of Scripture, all those
passages which attribute to God hands, feet, &c., and take them merely as
figures of speech. Such is the opinion of Alpakhar. In so far as he seeks to
explain Scripture by Scripture, I praise him, but I marvel that a man gifted
with reason should wish to debase that faculty. It is true that Scripture should
be explained by Scripture, so long as we are in difficulties about the meaning
and intention of the prophets, but when we have elicited the true meaning, we
must of necessity make use of our judgment and reason in order to assent thereto. If reason, however,
much as she rebels, is to be entirely subjected to Scripture, I ask, are we to
effect her submission by her own aid, or without her, and blindly? If the
latter, we shall surely act foolishly and injudiciously; if the former, we
assent to Scripture under the dominion of reason, and should not assent to it
without her. Moreover, I may ask now, is a man to assent to anything against his
reason? What is denial if it be not reason's refusal to
assent? In short, I am astonished that anyone should wish to subject reason, the greatest of gifts and a light from on high,
to the dead letter which may have been corrupted by human malice; that it should
be thought no crime to speak with contempt of mind, the true handwriting of
God's Word, calling it corrupt, blind, and lost, while it is considered the
greatest of crimes to say the same of the letter, which is merely the reflection
and image of God's Word. Men think it pious to trust nothing to reason and their own judgment, and impious to doubt the
faith of those who have transmitted to us the sacred books. Such conduct is not
piety, but mere folly. And, after all, why are they so anxious? What are they
afraid of? Do they think that faith and religion cannot be upheld unless - men
purposely keep themselves in ignorance, and turn their backs on reason? If this be so, they have but a timid trust in
Scripture.
However, be it far from me to say that religion should
seek to enslave reason, or reason religion, or that both should not be
able to keep their sovereignty in perfect harmony. I will revert to this
question presently, for I wish now to discuss Alpakhar's rule.
He requires, as we have stated, that we should accept
as true, or reject as false, everything asserted or denied by Scripture, and he
further states that Scripture never expressly asserts or denies anything which
contradicts its assertions or negations elsewhere. The rashness of such a
requirement and statement can escape no one. For (passing over the fact that he
does not notice that Scripture consists of different books, written at different
times, for different people, by different authors: and also that his requirement
is made on his own authority without any corroboration from reason or Scripture)
he would be bound to show that all passages which are indirectly contradictory
of the rest, can be satisfactorily explained metaphorically through the nature
of the language and the context: further, that Scripture has come down to us
untampered with. However, we will go into the matter at length.
Firstly, I ask what shall we do if reason prove recalcitrant? Shall we still be bound to
affirm whatever Scripture affirms, and to deny whatever Scripture denies?
Perhaps it will be answered that Scripture contains nothing repugnant to reason.
But I insist that it expressly affirms and teaches that God is jealous (namely,
in the decalogue itself, and in Exod. xxxiv:14, and in Deut. iv:24, and in many
other places), and I assert that such a doctrine is repugnant to reason. It
must, I suppose, in spite of all, be accepted as true. If there are any passages
in Scripture which imply that God is not jealous, they must be taken
metaphorically as meaning nothing of the kind. So, also, Scripture expressly
states (Exod. xix:20, &c.) that God came down to Mount Sinai, and it
attributes to Him other movements from place to place, nowhere directly stating
that God does not so move. Wherefore, we must take the passage literally, and
Solomon's words (I Kings viii:27), "But will God dwell on the earth? Behold the
heavens and earth cannot contain thee," inasmuch as they do not expressly state
that God does not move from place to place, but only imply it, must be explained
away till they have no further semblance of denying locomotion to the Deity. So
also we must believe that the sky is the habitation and throne of God, for
Scripture expressly says so; and similarly many passages expressing the opinions
of the prophets or the multitude, which reason and philosophy, but not Scripture, tell us to be false,
must be taken as true if we are to follow the guidance of our author, for
according to him, reason has nothing to do with the matter. Further, it is
untrue that Scripture never contradicts itself directly, but only by
implication. For Moses says, in so many words (Deut. iv:24), "The Lord
thy God is a consuming fire," and elsewhere expressly denies that God has any
likeness to visible things. (Deut. iv. 12.) If it be decided that the latter
passage only contradicts the former by implication, and must be adapted thereto,
lest it seem to negative it, let us grant that God is a fire; or rather, lest we
should seem to have taken leave of our senses, let us pass the matter over and
take another example.
Samuel expressly denies that God ever repents, "for he
is not a man that he should repent" (I Sam. xv:29). Jeremiah, on the other hand,
asserts that God does repent, both of the evil and of the good which He had
intended to do (Jer. xviii:8-10). What? Are not these two texts directly
contradictory? Which of the two, then, would our author want to explain
metaphorically? Both statements are general, and each is the opposite of the
other - what one flatly affirms, the other flatly, denies. So, by his own rule,
he would be obliged at once to reject them as false, and to accept them as true.
Again, what is the point of one passage, not being
contradicted by another directly, but only by implication, if the implication is
clear, and the nature and context of the passage preclude metaphorical
interpretation? There are many such instances in the Bible, as we saw in Chap.
2. (where we pointed out that the prophets held different and contradictory
opinions), and also in Chaps. IX. and X., where we drew attention to the
contradictions in the historical narratives. There is no need for me to go
through them all again, for what I have said sufficiently exposes the
absurdities which would follow from an opinion and rule such as we are
discussing, and shows the hastiness of its propounder.
We may, therefore, put this theory, as well as that of
Maimonides, entirely out of court; and we may, take it
for indisputable that theology is not bound to serve reason, nor reason theology, but that each has her own
domain.
The sphere of reason is, as we have said, truth and wisdom; the
sphere of theology, is piety and obedience. The power of reason
does not extend so far as to determine for us that men may be blessed through
simple obedience, without understanding. Theology, tells us nothing else, enjoins on us no
command save obedience, and has neither the will nor the power to oppose reason:
she defines the dogmas of faith (as we pointed out in the last chapter) only in
so far as they may be necessary, for obedience, and leaves reason to determine
their precise truth: for reason is the light of the mind, and without her all
things are dreams and phantoms.
By theology, I here mean, strictly speaking, revelation, in so far as it indicates the object aimed
at by Scripture namely, the scheme and manner of obedience, or the true dogmas
of piety and faith. This may truly be called the Word of God, which does not
consist in a certain number of books (see Chap. 12.). Theology thus understood, if we regard its precepts or
rules of life, will be found in accordance with reason; and, if we look to its aim and object, will be
seen to be in nowise repugnant thereto, wherefore it is universal to all men.
As for its bearing on Scripture, we have shown in
Chap. 7. that the meaning of Scripture should be gathered from its own history,
and not from the history of nature in general, which is the basis of philosophy.
We ought not to be hindered if we find that our
investigation of the meaning of Scripture thus conducted shows us that it is
here and there repugnant to reason; for whatever we may find of this sort in the
Bible, which men may be in ignorance of, without injury to their charity, has,
we may be sure, no bearing on theology or the Word of God, and may, therefore,
without blame, be viewed by every one as he pleases.
To sum up, we may draw the absolute conclusion that
the Bible must not be accommodated to reason, nor reason to the Bible.
Now, inasmuch as the basis of theology - the doctrine that man may be saved by
obedience alone - cannot be proved by reason whether it be true or false, we may be asked,
Why, then, should we believe it? If we do so without the aid of reason, we accept it blindly, and act foolishly and
injudiciously; if, on the other hand, we settle that it can be proved by reason,
theology becomes a part of philosophy, and inseparable therefrom. But I make
answer that I have absolutely established that this basis of theology cannot be
investigated by the natural light of reason, or, at any rate, that no one ever has proved it
by such means, and, therefore, revelation was necessary. We should, however, make use
of our reason, in order to grasp with moral certainty what is revealed - I say,
with moral certainty, for we cannot hope to attain greater certainty, than the
prophets: yet their certainty was only, moral, as I showed in Chap. 2.
Those, therefore, who attempt to set forth the
authority of Scripture with mathematical demonstrations are wholly in error: for
the authority, of the Bible is dependent on the authority of the prophets, and
can be supported by no stronger arguments than those employed in old time by the
prophets for convincing the people of their own authority. Our certainty on the
same subject can be founded on no other basis than that which served as
foundation for the certainty of the prophets.
Now the certainty of the prophets consisted (as we
pointed out) in these elements:-
(I.) A distinct and vivid imagination.
(II.) A sign.
(III.) Lastly, and
chiefly, a mind turned to what is just and good. It was based on no other
reasons than these, and consequently they cannot prove their authority by any
other reasons, either to the multitude whom they addressed orally, nor to us
whom they address in writing.
The first of these reasons, namely, the vivid imagination, could be valid only for the prophets;
therefore, our certainty concerning revelation must, and ought to be, based on the
remaining two - namely, the sign and the teaching. Such is the express doctrine
of Moses, for (in Deut. xviii.) he bids the people obey
the prophet who should give a true sign in the name of the Lord, but if he
should predict falsely, even though it were in the name of the Lord, he should
be put to death, as should also he who strives to lead away the people from the
true religion, though he confirm his authority with signs and portents. We may
compare with the above Deut. xiii. Whence it follows that a true prophet could
be distinguished from a false one, both by his doctrine and by the miracles he wrought, for Moses declares such an one to be a true prophet, and
bids the people trust him without fear of deceit. He condemns as false, and
worthy, of death, those who predict anything falsely even in the name of the
Lord, or who preach false gods, even though their miracles be real.
The only reason, then, which we have for belief in
Scripture or the writings of the prophets, is the doctrine we find therein, and
the signs by which it is confirmed. For as we see that the prophets extol
charity and justice above all things, and have no other object, we conclude that
they did not write from unworthy motives, but because they really thought that
men might become blessed through obedience and faith: further, as we see that
they confirmed their teaching with signs and wonders, we become persuaded that
they did not speak at random, nor run riot in their prophecies. We are further
strengthened in our conclusion by the fact that the morality they teach is in
evident agreement with reason, for it is no accidental coincidence that the
Word of God which we find in the prophets coincides with the Word of God written
in our hearts. We may, I say, conclude this from the sacred books as certainly
as did the Jews of old from the living voice of the prophets: for we showed in
Chap. 12. that Scripture has come down to us intact in respect to its doctrine
and main narratives.
Therefore this whole basis of theology and Scripture, though it does not admit of
mathematical proof, may yet be accepted with the approval of our judgment. It
would be folly to refuse to accept what is confirmed by such ample prophetic
testimony, and what has proved such a comfort to those whose reason is comparatively weak, and such a benefit to the
state; a doctrine, moreover, which we may believe in without the slightest peril
or hurt, and should reject simply because it cannot be mathematically proved: it
is as though we should admit nothing as true, or as a wise rule of life, which
could ever, in any possible way, be called in question; or as though most of our
actions were not full of uncertainty and hazards.
I admit that those who believe that theology and philosophy are mutually contradictory, and that
therefore either one or the other must be thrust from its throne - I admit, I
say, that such persons are not unreasonable in attempting to put theology on a
firm basis, and to demonstrate its truth mathematically. Who, unless he were
desperate or mad, would wish to bid an incontinent farewell to reason, or to despise the arts and sciences, or to deny
reason's certitude? But, in the meanwhile, we cannot wholly absolve them from
blame, inasmuch as they invoke the aid of reason for her own defeat, and attempt infallibly to
prove her fallible. While they are trying to prove mathematically the authority
and truth of theology, and to take away the authority of natural reason, they are in reality only bringing theology
under reason's dominion, and proving that her authority has no weight unless
natural reason be at the back of it.
If they boast that they themselves assent because of the inward testimony of the Holy Spirit, and that they only invoke the aid of reason because of unbelievers, in order to convince them, not even so can this meet with our approval, for we can easily show that they have spoken either from emotion or vain-glory. It most clearly follows from the last chapter that the Holy Spirit only gives its testimony in favour of works, called by Paul (in Gal. v:22) the fruits of the Spirit, and is in itself really nothing but the mental acquiescence which follows a good action in our souls. No spirit gives testimony concerning the certitude of matters within the sphere of speculation, save only reason, who is mistress, as we have shown, of the whole realm of truth. If then they assert that they possess this Spirit which makes them certain of truth, they speak falsely, and according to the prejudices of the emotions, or else they are in great dread lest they should be vanquished by philosophers and exposed to public ridicule, and therefore they flee, as it were, to the altar; but their refuge is vain, for what altar will shelter a man who has outraged reason? However, I pass such persons over, for I think I have fulfilled my purpose, and shown how philosophy should be separated from theology, and wherein each consists; that neither should be subservient to the other, but that each should keep her unopposed dominion. Lastly, as occasion offered, I have pointed out the absurdities, the inconveniences, and the evils following from the extraordinary confusion which has hitherto prevailed between the two subjects, owing to their not being properly distinguished and separated. Before I go further I would expressly state (though I have said it before) that I consider the utility and the need for Holy Scripture or Revelation to be very great. For as we cannot perceive by the natural light of reason that simple obedience is the path of salvation [N25], and are taught by revelation only that it is so by the special grace of God, which our reason cannot attain, it follows that the Bible has brought a very great consolation to mankind. All are able to obey, whereas there are but very few, compared with the aggregate of humanity, who can acquire the habit of virtue under the unaided guidance of reason. Thus if we had not the testimony of Scripture, we should doubt of the salvation of nearly all men.
[Note N25]: "That simple obedience is the path of salvation." In other words, it is enough for salvation or blessedness, that we should embrace the Divine decrees as laws or commands; there is no need to conceive them as eternal truths. This can be taught us by Revelation, not Reason, as appears from the demonstrations given in Chapter 4.