|
Iraqi
civilians gather near the site of where a bus was shot on a
bridge by a tank crew from the U.S. Army 4th Battalion 64 Armor
Regiment in Baghdad Friday, April 11, 2003. Tank commander Charles
Wooten said that his tank fired on the vehicle after it refused
to stop when warning shots were fired. The bus driver was killed
and the Army said it found Iraqi military uniforms inside the
vehicle.(AP Photo/John Moore) |
During
the euphoria of the opening air campaign against Baghdad, commentary
was filled with triumphal rhetoric about hitting ''legitimate military
objectives'' while causing little or even no loss of civilian life.
Not long afterward, the air war was pounding more than symbols of
the regime, and the ground war had become a real war. Scarcely a
speech, briefing or interview was being given that failed to mention
the laws of war. The Iraqi regime, for its part, was broadcasting
denunciations of American airstrikes replete with images of corpses
and wounded civilians in hospitals; the United States responded
that Iraq had systematically situated military targets and equipment
in the midst of civilian areas. The sheer frequency of these references
on all sides belied the ancient maxim inter arma silent leges
-- in time of war law is silent.
People
throughout the world obviously care about what is called jus
in bello, law governing conduct during war. This is so even
if they differ about jus ad bellum, law governing not the
conduct of war but rather the resort to force itself. But even while
there is agreement on the need for fundamental rules governing the
conduct of war, there is profound disagreement over who has authority
to declare, interpret and enforce those rules, as well as who --
and what developments in the so-called art of war -- will shape
them now and into the future. In short, who ''owns'' the law of
war?
The
Roots of the Modern Law of War
Although
most of the world's religious and ethical traditions, if they admit
the moral possibility of war at all, say something about what conduct
is permitted in war, modern law of war descended historically as
a tenet of traditional Christian just-war theory. The practical
expression of such law, however, began with the founding of the
International Committee of the Red Cross in 1863. The moving force
behind the establishment of the Red Cross was Henri Dunant, a Genevan
who witnessed and later wrote a widely read account of the Battle
of Solferino in the 1859 war between Austria and France. Dunant,
together with inhabitants of a village near the battlefield, went
about the appalling task of trying to tend to the thousands of wounded
who had simply been left to die.
Without
bandages, stretchers, doctors or medicines, and above all without
significant interest in the wounded by their governments, there
was little to be done except offer water and prayer. In the aftermath,
the Red Cross, organized to do what had not been done at Solferino,
became the world's first secular international nongovernmental organization,
the ur-N.G.O. One of its goals was self-contradictory and even ludicrous
on its face -- to bring humanity to the battlefield -- but its idealism
was expressive of a sweeping call for reform among the middle classes
in late-19th-century Europe and America, where an indigenous humanitarian
movement for the care of soldiers had taken root during the Civil
War.
In
Europe, the same spirit of reform touched governments and royal
courts, as a series of diplomatic conferences set about codifying
the centuries-long tradition of ''laws and customs of war.'' The
most important result was the 1907 Hague Convention, which in 56
short articles covers vast legal terrain on the conduct of warfare
-- including surrender and flags of truce, obligations to wear uniforms,
treatment of prisoners of war, sieges and bombardments, protection
of cultural property, prohibitions against pillage and terms of
occupation.
Its
general rules are still applicable, at least in principle, today.
Indeed, most of the matters that coalition forces raise as violations
of the laws of war by Iraqi forces -- perfidious surrender, fighting
out of uniform or mistreatment of P.O.W.'s -- can be found somewhere
in the Hague regulations.
Optimism
was swept away a few years later, however, by the guns of August.
During World War I, in which mustard gas, aerial warfare, tanks
and, above all, the machine gun, were introduced, old rules were
clearly no longer enough, and existing humanitarian organizations
were simply unable to cope with suffering on a scale never before
seen. Following the Great War, there was a resurgence of interest
in the fields of jus ad bellum and jus in bello. The
Red Cross built on its earlier work in fostering treaties for sick
and wounded soldiers and moved directly into promoting humanitarianism
in war through legal rules, convening meetings between states that
eventually resulted in the Geneva Conventions of 1929. These conventions,
along with the 1907 Hague Convention, were the primary codified
laws of war in effect when World War II broke out. In addition,
states negotiated the 1925 Geneva Protocol prohibiting gas weapons
-- a ban that held with few exceptions, even during World War II,
for 60 years, until Saddam Hussein broke it in the Iran-Iraq war
and again in his genocidal 1988 Anfal campaign against the Kurds.
World
War II and its Aftermath
World
War II brought its own violations, partly owing to the new technology
of air war against civilians. The carpet-bombing of Dresden, for
instance, inevitably swept civilians in with soldiers as targets.
The conclusion of World War II brought about two signal developments
in the laws of war. The first was the holding of criminal trials
by the victors of those deemed to be chiefly responsible for the
war. We tend to think of the Nuremberg trials as war-crimes trials,
but in fact Nuremberg was principally about trying German leaders
for the crime of aggressive war, for making war itself, crimes of
jus ad bellum, rather than for the manner of its conduct.
The chief American prosecutor, Robert Jackson, was content to leave
what he regarded as the legally less-cutting-edge matters, the war's
atrocities, to prosecutors from other countries.
Jackson's
seeming triumph at Nuremberg, however -- establishing that international
judges could try and convict a nation's leaders for the crime of
aggression -- did not survive the establishment of the United Nations
and the Security Council. The matter of determining aggression and
maintaining international peace was stripped from international
jurists and thrust into the hands of the permanent members of the
Security Council, victors of World War II.
Of
course, the Security Council, far from maintaining peace and security,
has served as little more than a talking shop for nearly all of
its history. The willingness of one of the permanent five members
to brush off the Security Council when its core national interests
are threatened -- as the United States and Britain just did with
respect to Iraq -- is a norm of the Security Council, not a departure
from it. Every permanent member has such interests, which are not
necessarily even questions of national security but are frequently
matters of ambition or even sentimental attachment. They include
Tibet and Taiwan for the Chinese; Chechnya and, in 1999, Serbia
for the Russians; and Francophone Africa for the French.
The
enduring law established at Nuremberg has thus turned out not to
be the ''crime of aggression'' but a reaffirmation of war crimes
as traditionally understood -- with two important innovations made
necessary by the Nazi death camps: genocide and crimes against humanity.
Nuremberg also had serious gaps. Most significant, it failed to
address the terror bombing of civilians and the deliberate consuming
of whole cities (Dresden, Tokyo) by fire -- the most enthusiastic
practitioners of the latter being the Allies.
The
failure to prosecute the Allies for firebombing cities is one of
the strongest arguments today for why war-crimes tribunals should
not be conducted by the victors. Many regard this argument as so
clinching, in fact, that the mere charge of ''victor's justice''
is enough to end debate. Yet it is far from obvious to me that ''impartial,''
uninvolved parties automatically carry greater moral authority than
victors. Would it have been morally better, for example, for the
victors of World War II, who had paid the price in blood, to have
handed justice over to those countries that had remained neutral
and refused to become involved? What matters far more than the supposedly
virtuous impartiality that comes from neutrality is the quality
of justice served in each case.
The
Geneva Conventions of 1949
Another
development in the laws of war following World War II was the four
Geneva Conventions of 1949 -- the first covering wounded or sick
soldiers; the second, shipwrecked sailors; the third, prisoners
of war; and the fourth, civilians and occupation. The Geneva Conventions
also introduced, for the first time in the canonical laws-of-war
treaties, individual criminal liability and mandatory ''universal
jurisdiction'' -- the ability (indeed, the obligation) of any and
every state to try individuals (or turn them over to a state that
would) whenever there was evidence of ''grave breaches'' of the
Geneva Conventions.
The
question of who is qualified to assert jurisdiction and then judge
cases of war crimes is vital to determining who owns the laws of
war. Universal jurisdiction says, in effect, lots of people own
the laws -- but it leaves open the possibility of widely differing
interpretations. A case in point is the continuing argument over
whether the detainees at Guantanamo are indeed bona fide P.O.W.'s
being mistreated under the Third Geneva Convention, as Amnesty International
argues; or whether the Taliban among them are P.O.W.'s but some
members of Al Qaeda are not, as Human Rights Watch says; or whether
none of them are P.O.W.'s at all, as the Bush administration insists.
Related to this is the question of whether detainees can be determined
not to be P.O.W.'s by any means other than individual hearings.
Many human rights advocates simply assume that the determination
of whether a detainee is a P.O.W. must be reached by an individual
hearing. This is a reading of the treaty with which even many conservatives
agree. (Indeed, it is the reading presumed in 1997 United States
military regulations that long precede Sept. 11.) But while it is
surely the best interpretation of the Third Geneva Convention, it
is not necessarily the way a literal reader would interpret phrases
in Article 5's language like ''competent tribunal'' and ''should
any doubt arise.'' It is (barely, but literally) available to the
Bush administration to maintain that a) no doubt arises as to the
status of the prisoners at Guantanamo and that b) the determination
of whether any doubt has arisen does not necessarily require a hearing
by a ''competent tribunal'' but merely a finding by the secretary
of defense or the president.
This
apparently esoteric legal issue, seemingly nothing but sheer technicality,
is important. Why? It is not because it prevents someone from being
charged with war crimes -- anyone can be charged with war crimes
-- but because those determined not to be bona fide P.O.W.'s have
far fewer procedural rights at trial. Bona fide P.O.W.'s (even those
charged with war crimes) must be given the same legal protections
at trial that an American soldier, accused of the same crime, would
be given (and these are considerable), whereas an ''unprivileged
combatant'' receives only minimal due process protections. The issue
is about to arise again, this time in connection with Iraq's fedayeen
militia fighters, who wear no uniforms and therefore might not qualify
as bona fide P.O.W.'s, some of whom may be transferred shortly to
Guantanamo.
This
dispute points, in addition, to an unsettling feature about the
struggle over who ''owns'' the law of war. The various constituencies
that believe it belongs to them -- in this case, the United States
government on the one side and human rights organizations on the
other -- feel little obligation to acknowledge frankly the arguments
made against their legal interpretations.
Fundamental
Principles and Moral Calculation
Despite
these struggles over authority to interpret the 1949 Geneva Conventions,
they are accepted universally as binding law on the treatment of
people under a particular status -- soldier, sailor, P.O.W., civilian.
The fundamental moral and legal principles are plain. First, noncombatants
may never be made the object or target of attack, nor may noncombatants
ever be used by defenders to shield legitimate military objectives
from attack. Second, military operations, whether by attackers or
defenders, must be undertaken with care to distinguish between noncombatants
and combatants. Moreover, military officials must refrain from operations
likely to produce collateral civilian damage that is excessive relative
to the military advantages. So, for example, if the Iraqi Republican
Guard has based itself in a crowded Baghdad neighborhood -- and
even if it has done so illegally, by refusing to order or even allow
civilians to evacuate, in order to use civilians as a shield --
the United States must still weigh the military advantages of attacking
against the probable cost of civilian deaths and injuries.
The
first principle is categorical, admitting of no exceptions. It leads
in turn to a cluster of specific, categorical requirements aimed
at ensuring that noncombatants or soldiers who are no longer in
combat, like P.O.W.'s, are not attacked -- for example, requirements
that combatants wear uniforms or other identifying marks and carry
weapons openly. Although some of these categorical obligations have
ambiguities -- what qualifies as a uniform? -- and although evidence,
interpretation and intent might complicate matters, in principle
they are either adhered to or not.
The
second principle -- refraining from causing excessive collateral
civilian damage -- involves, by contrast, a weighing of costs and
benefits and, making things still more difficult, those costs and
benefits as they might accrue in the future. Every day, every night,
Air Force lawyers and planners must consider possible targets and
weigh what they think the military value might be, in the future
course of war, against the best intelligence data on how many civilians
might be killed or injured, or how much civilian property destroyed.
It is a thankless game of guesswork. By their nature, such judgments
involve factual evaluations and guesses that cannot be legally challenged,
unless something approximating willful, intentional gross negligence
can be shown. Gross negligence has to consist of more than a lot
of collateral damage, including gruesome civilian death and injury,
that might be the result simply of a cruise missile aimed in good
faith but gone astray. Legal culpability cannot be determined simply
by looking at the level of damage and the death and injury caused.
There is no moral equivalence between stray missiles aimed in good
faith, using the best technology available, and deliberate violation
of the categorical rules of war, like using human shields, shelling
civilians to prevent them from fleeing Basra and rape or summary
execution of prisoners. There can be no element of judgment, or
weighing of costs and benefits, in deciding whether or not to target
civilians or take them hostage; it is always wrong.
And
yet. The reality remains for many that this moral distinction is
sophistry. How can it not be, when we see every day on television
and in the newspapers (especially non-American ones) so much death
and injury to civilians? To speak of ''aiming'' at one thing while
simultaneously foreseeing that, in a sizable percentage of cases,
you would ''accidentally'' hit another -- if this is what ''rules''
of war consist of, then they are no more than artificial salves
on the consciences of combatants.
Moreover,
it does seem to millions of people worldwide that there is indeed
a moral equivalence between the tactics of the Americans -- hitting
targets from the air and pleading collateral damage as a defense
against responsibility -- and the tactics of the Iraqis, who, lacking
other means to attack, use their own civilians as a material and
moral resource, no matter what laws of war it might violate. This
was the attitude, it should be said, held by Churchill, who intended
a scorched-earth defense of Britain (including the use of poison
gas) without much regard for the lives of British civilians, should
the invader ever arrive.
There
is, I think, only one way to evaluate these conflicting claims.
The idea of ''acceptable'' collateral damage is firmly embedded
in Western legal and moral thought, but in fact it is the product
of a far more particular Christian strand of moral thought than
many of us, accustomed to the tradition, readily admit. The ''doctrine
of the double-effect,'' turning on a supposed moral difference between
intended and unintended but foreseeable consequences, is not morally
obvious. It can be defended, however, as a moral doctrine if we
consider the alternatives. To deny the distinction means that you
either accept that virtual non-violence is the only tenable position
or that you are indifferent to the lives of civilians, since you
are guilty of anything that happens anyway -- and in that case,
anything becomes a target. The justification for the principle of
the double-effect is that it appears to be the only principled way
of steering between a pacifism that few of us, in real life, would
accept, and a brutal realism that denies the moral necessity of
even trying to distinguish between combatants and non-combatants.
Even
if you accept the principle of this distinction, however, it must
be with a knowledge that it is a compromise affair. It therefore
puts a great moral burden on those who fight to find better ways
to separate civilians from fighters and to improve the ability,
through technology or other means, to aim and hit solely military
targets. And if war is, as the poet Rene Char wrote, ''this time
of damned algebra,'' a matter of endless calculation and recalculation
of effects, then the law of war must take that into account. It
consists on the one hand of both categorical demands and prohibitions,
and on the other of calculations of cost and benefit, civilian loss
and military advantage -- and these calculations are always in flux.
New
Treaties and New Debates
The
attempt to address these complexities and make law of them was undertaken
by United Nations negotiations in the 1970's. The 1977 Additional
Protocol I grew out of these negotiations. Although now ratified
by some 160 nations with varying ''reservations'' (statements as
to certain treaty articles a country does not accept as binding),
the United States has never ratified it (nor, it should be noted,
has Iraq). Yet without accepting the treaty as such, United States
officials over the past 20 years have indicated that the United
States accepts various parts of the treaty without accepting the
whole. It remains a disappointment and a puzzle that the Department
of Defense has never been willing to state publicly and definitively
which parts it accepts and which parts it does not and why.
But
the American problems with Protocol I generally fall into three
main categories. First, certain provisions are unacceptably political
in nature. Jus in bello has always insisted on exactly the
same treatment for all sides in combat, the same rules whether for
the Allies or for the Germans, communists or capitalists. Protocol
I, however, grants combatants rights, including the vital right
to be treated as a P.O.W., on the basis of certain motives for fighting,
referring specifically to those who fight against ''racist regimes''
(as in South Africa under apartheid) or ''alien occupation'' (as
in Israel).
Second,
certain provisions appear to the United States to restrict methods
and means of warfare that it believes are legitimate. For example,
Protocol I contains no exceptions in its rules for nuclear weapons,
while at the same time it categorically prohibits reprisals against
civilians, including the use of nuclear weapons in reprisal for
a nuclear attack, which is the basis for nuclear deterrence.
The
third category of America's objections concerns rules in Protocol
I that are aimed at accommodating guerrillas and irregular fighters,
as during the Vietnam War or in Iraq. Unquestionably, these rules
make life legally easier for irregular fighters, and some would
see this as making the rules of war more ''fair.'' Yet the rules
also create new risks for civilians. For example, the protocol grants
legal combatant status even to guerrillas who conceal themselves
and their weapons among the civilian population, as long as the
fighters reveal themselves to the adversary ''preceding the launching
of an attack'' -- which is to say, often shortly before attacking
from among the civilians who will, inevitably, be caught in the
crossfire. It is unfortunate for Saddam's irregulars that Iraq and
the United States have not ratified the protocol, as it would have
provided legal protection for many of those fighters' attacks, if
surely not the civilians providing them with cover.
In
addition, sections of Protocol I, while dealing with indiscriminate
attacks -- military operations that fail to distinguish between
combatants and noncombatants -- in detail, mention the obligations
of defenders far more briefly. This is despite the fact that
the level of collateral damage incurred in military operations is
often determined by where the defender chooses to locate
its military assets.
And
so Amnesty International released a report last year on the actions
of the Israeli Defense Forces in Jenin that signally failed even
to mention the legal obligations of the Palestinian forces toward
their own civilians. Human Rights Watch also issued an entire report
on Jenin that raised only in a few sentences the fact that Palestinian
fighters had situated themselves among civilians. (To Human Rights
Watch's credit, and perhaps in response to criticism, it has begun
taking careful note of the obligations of forces on the defensive
as well as those of attackers.) And the International Red Cross,
in a message from its president at the commencement of the Iraq
war, called in general terms upon parties to observe the laws of
war but dwelt mainly upon attackers, the United States and Britain,
neglecting to say anything specific of the Iraqi defenders. But
the inescapable fact is that the structure of Protocol I practically
invites such neglect.
The
Laws of War Reconsidered
The
fact remains that every war is a petri dish for the next round of
the laws of war. And while the war in Iraq is principally about
well-established legal principles, and their violation, it, too,
will end with a reconsideration of the laws dictating how war should
be waged.
For
the past 20 years, the center of gravity in establishing, interpreting
and shaping the law of war has gradually shifted away from the military
establishments of leading states and their ''state practice.'' It
has even shifted away from the International Red Cross (invested
by the Geneva Conventions with special authority) and toward more
activist and publicly aggressive N.G.O.'s -- including the ad hoc
coalitions that produced the Ottawa Treaty, banning land mines,
and the new International Criminal Court. These N.G.O.'s are indispensable
in advancing the cause of humanitarianism in war. But the pendulum
shift toward them has gone further than is useful, and the ownership
of the laws of war needs to give much greater weight to the state
practices of leading countries. This does not mean that state practice
is all that matters, nor does it mean that all state practice matters
-- Iraq, after all, is a state, and it is fighting, too -- but it
does mean that the state practice of democratic sovereigns that
actually fight wars should be ascendant in shaping the law. And
this includes raising the standards of the laws of war to reflect,
for example, advances in technology and precision weapons, standards
that should become the norm for leading militaries, first for NATO
and then beyond.
N.G.O.'s
are also wedded far too much to a procedural preference for the
international over the national. But that agenda increasingly amounts
to internationalism for its own sake, and its specific purpose is
to constrain American sovereignty. It thus promotes, embedded in
an agenda of human rights and the laws of war, the ceding of sovereignty,
even democratic sovereignty, as the most virtuous act that a state
can perform on behalf of its citizens. This agenda of privileging
internationalism, unfortunately, is even sometimes allowed to override
obvious steps backward in the laws of war, like privileging guerrilla
combatants over the civilians in their midst. For this reason, one
consequence of the Iraq war for the future of the laws of war will
have to be an understanding that the solicitude of Protocol I for
irregular fighters hiding among civilians is wrong and that the
United States was right to have rejected it.
More
broadly in recent years, the N.G.O.'s have been promoting an ever
more utopian law of war, in keeping with absolutist human rights
ideology. In practice, alas, this utopianism is aimed only at one
side in conflicts -- the side that in fact tries to obey the law.
And so a second consequence of the war in Iraq for the future of
the law of war will have to be a halt to raising the standards ever
higher for protecting the civilian population when that burden effectively
falls only on attacking forces, unreciprocated. The status quo has
the effect of rewarding defending forces for recognizing that war
crimes against their own civilians are the best strategy against
a powerful but scrupulous enemy. It risks in the end creating a
law of war that assumes, for all practical purposes, that the burden
is all on one side, the side with the more advanced technology and
the less desperate military. After the last cruise missile has been
launched and the last irregular fighter silenced, we will look back
on the war that was wrought. What we will find is that the meaning
of ''asymmetric'' warfare is not what we thought. The issue is not
so much disparities in technology. Instead, a form of warfare has
re-emerged that tacitly assumes, indeed permits, that the weaker
side must fight by using systematic violations of the law and its
method. This is unsustainable as a basis for the law of war. Reciprocity
matters.
Kenneth
Anderson is a law professor at American University and a research
fellow at the Hoover Institution, Stanford University. He was legal
editor of the book ''Crimes of War: What the Public Should Know.''
This
article first appeared in a slightly different form in the New York
Times Magazine on Sunday April 13, 2003.
The
Crimes of War Project would welcome responses to the arguments made
in this essay. Please submit them to our web editor, Anthony Dworkin
at anthony@crimesofwar.org
Back to Top
|