Encyclopaedia of
the Philosophical Sciences (1830) Part One
I. Introduction
¤1
Philosophy
misses an advantage enjoyed by the other sciences. It cannot like them rest the
existence of its objects on the natural admissions of consciousness, nor can it
assume that its method of cognition, either for starting or
for continuing, is one already accepted. The objects of philosophy, it is true,
are upon the whole the same as those of religion. In both the object is
Truth, in that supreme sense in which God and God only is the Truth. Both in like manner go
on to treat of the finite worlds of Nature and the human Mind, with their relation to
each other and to their truth in God. Some acquaintance with its
objects, therefore, philosophy may and even must presume, that and a certain
interest in them to boot, were it for no other reason than this: that in point
of time the mind makes general images of objects, long before it
makes notions of them, and that it is
only through these mental images, and by recourse to them, that the thinking
mind rises to know and comprehend thinkingly.
But with the
rise of this thinking study of things, it soon becomes evident that thought
will be satisfied with nothing short of showing the necessity of its facts, of
demonstrating the existence of its objects, as well as their nature and
qualities. Our original acquaintance with them is thus discovered to be
inadequate. We can assume nothing and assert nothing dogmatically; nor can we accept the
assertions and assumptions of others. And yet we must make a beginning: and a
beginning, as primary and underived, makes an
assumption, or rather is an assumption. It seems as if it were impossible to
make a beginning at all.
¤ 2
This thinking
study of things may serve, in a general way, as a description of
philosophy. But the description is too wide. If it be correct to say, that
thought makes the distinction between man and the lower animals, then
everything human is human, for the sole and simple reason that it is due to the
operation of thought. Philosophy, on the other hand, is a peculiar mode of
thinking — a mode in which thinking becomes knowledge, and knowledge
through notions. However great therefore may be the identity and essential
unity of the two modes of thought, the philosophic mode gets to be different from
the more general thought which acts in all that is human, in all that gives
humanity its distinctive character. And this difference connects itself with
the fact that the strictly human and thought-induced phenomena of consciousness
do not originally appear in the form of a thought, but as a feeling, a
perception, or mental image — all of which aspects must be distinguished
from the form of thought proper.
According to
an old preconceived idea, which has passed into a trivial proposition, it is
thought which marks the man off from the animals. Yet trivial as this old
belief may seem, it must, strangely enough, be recalled to mind in presence of
certain preconceived ideas of the present day. These ideas would put feeling
and thought so far apart as to make them opposites, and would represent them as
so antagonistic, that feeling, particularly religious feeling, is supposed to
be contaminated, perverted, and even annihilated by thought. They also
emphatically hold that religion and piety grow out of, and rest upon something
else, and not on thought. But those who make this separation forget meanwhile
that only man has the capacity for religion, and that animals no more have
religion than they have law and morality.
Those who
insist on this separation of religion from thinking usually have before their
minds the sort of thought that may be styled after-thought. They
mean ÔreflectiveÕ thinking, which has to deal with thoughts as thoughts, and
brings them into consciousness. Slackness to perceive and keep in view this
distinction which philosophy definitely draws in respect of thinking is the
source of the crudest objections and reproaches against philosophy. Man —
and that just because it is his nature to think — is the only being that
possesses law, religion, and morality. In these spheres of human life,
therefore, thinking, under the guise of feeling, faith, or generalised
image, has not been inactive: its action and its productions are there present
and therein contained. But it is one thing to have such feelings and generalised images that have been moulded
and permeated by thought, and another thing to have thoughts about them. The
thoughts, to which after-thought upon those modes of consciousness gives rise,
are what is comprised under reflection, general reasoning, and the like, as
well as under philosophy itself.
The neglect
of this distinction between thought in general and the reflective thought of
philosophy has also led to another and more frequent misunderstanding. Reflection of this kind has been
often maintained to be the condition, or even the only way, of attaining a
consciousness and certitude of the Eternal and True. The (now somewhat
antiquated) metaphysical proofs of GodÕs
existence, for example, have been treated, as if a knowledge of them and a
conviction of their truth were the only and essential means of producing a
belief and conviction that there is a God. Such a doctrine would find its
parallel, if we said that eating was impossible before we had acquired a
knowledge of the chemical, botanical, and zoological characters of our food;
and that we must delay digestion till we had finished the study of anatomy and
physiology. Were it so, these sciences in their field, like philosophy in its,
would gain greatly in point of utility; in fact, their utility would rise to
the height of absolute and universal indispensableness. Or rather, instead of
being indispensable, they would not exist at all.
¤ 3
The Content, of whatever kind it
be, with which our consciousness is taken up, is what constitutes the qualitative character of our
feelings, perceptions, fancies, and ideas; of our aims and duties; and of our
thoughts and notions. From this point of view, feeling, perception, etc., are
the forms assumed by these contents. The contents remain one and
the same, whether they are felt, seen, represented, or willed, and whether they
are merely felt, or felt with an admixture of thoughts, or merely and simply
thought. In any one of these forms, or in the admixture of several, the
contents confront consciousness, or are its object. But when they
are thus objects of consciousness, the modes of the several forms ally
themselves with the contents; and each form of them appears in consequence to
give rise to a special object. Thus what is the same at bottom may look like a
different sort of fact.
The several
modes of feeling, perception, desire, and will, so far as we are aware
of them, are in general called ideas (mental representations): and it may be
roughly said that philosophy puts thoughts, categories, or, in more precise
language, adequate notions, in the place of the generalised images we ordinarily call ideas. Mental
impressions such as these may be regarded as the metaphors of thoughts and
notions. But to have these figurate conceptions does not imply that we
appreciate their intellectual significance, the thoughts and rational notions
to which they correspond. Conversely, it is one thing to have thoughts and
intelligent notions, and another to know what impressions, perceptions, and
feelings correspond to them.
This
difference will to some extent explain what people call the unintelligibility
of philosophy. Their difficulty lies partly in an incapacity — which in
itself is nothing but want of habit — for abstract thinking; i.e. in an
inability to get hold of pure thoughts and move about in them. In our ordinary
state of mind, the thoughts are clothed upon and made one with the sensuous or
spiritual material of the hour; and in reflection, meditation, and general reasoning,
we introduce a blend of thoughts into feelings, percepts, and mental images.
(Thus, in propositions where the subject-matter is due to the senses —
e.g. ÔThis leaf is greenÕ — we have such categories introduced, as being
and individuality.) But it is a very different thing to make the thoughts pure
and simple our object.
But their
complaint that philosophy is unintelligible is as much due to another reason;
and that is an impatient wish to have before them as a mental picture that
which is in the mind as a thought or notion. When people are asked to apprehend
some notion, they often complain that they do not know what they have to think.
But the fact is that in a notion there is nothing further to be thought than
the notion itself. What the phrase reveals is a hankering after an image with
which we are already familiar. The mind, denied the use of its familiar ideas,
feels the ground where it once stood firm and at home taken away from beneath
it, and, when transported into the region of pure thought, cannot tell where in
the world it is.
One
consequence of this weakness is that authors, preachers, and orators are found
most intelligible, when they speak of things which their readers or hearers
already know by rote — things which the latter are conversant with, and
which require no explanation.
¤ 4
The
philosopher then has to reckon with popular modes of thought, and with the
objects of religion. In dealing with the ordinary modes of mind, he will first
of all, as we saw, have to prove and almost to awaken the need for his peculiar
method of knowledge. In dealing with the objects of religion, and with truth as
a whole, he will have to show that philosophy is capable of apprehending them
from its own resources; and should a difference from religious conceptions come
to light, he will have to justify the points in which it diverges.
¤ 5
To give the
reader a preliminary explanation of the distinction thus made, and to let him
see at the same moment that the real import of our consciousness is retained,
and even for the first time put in its proper light, when translated into the
form of thought and the notion of reason, it may be well to recall another of
these old unreasoned beliefs. And that is the conviction that to get at the
truth of any object or event, even of feelings, perceptions, opinions, and
mental ideas, we must think it over. Now in any case to think things over is at
least to transform feelings, ordinary ideas, etc. into thoughts.
Nature has
given every one a faculty of thought. But thought is all that philosophy claims
as the form proper to her business: and thus the inadequate view which ignores
the distinction stated in ¤3 leads to a new delusion, the reverse of the
complaint previously mentioned about the unintelligibility of philosophy. In
other words, this science must often submit to the slight of hearing even
people who have never taken any trouble with it talking as if they thoroughly
understood all about it. With no preparation beyond an ordinary education they
do not hesitate, especially under the influence of religious sentiment, to philosophise and to criticise
philosophy. Everybody allows that to know any other science you must have first
studied it, and that you can only claim to express a judgment upon it in virtue
of such knowledge. Everybody allows that to make a shoe you must have learned
and practised the craft of the shoemaker, though
every man has a model in his own foot, and possesses in his hands the natural
endowments for the operations required. For philosophy alone, it seems to be
imagined, such study, care, and application are not in the least requisite.
This
comfortable view of what is required for a philosopher has recently received
corroboration through the theory of immediate or intuitive knowledge.
¤ 6
So much for
the form of philosophical knowledge. It is no less desirable, on the other
hand, that philosophy should understand that its content is no other than actuality, that core of truth
which, originally produced and producing itself within the precincts of the
mental life, has become the world, the inward and outward world,
of consciousness. At first we become aware of these contents in what we call Experience. But even Experience,
as it surveys the wide range of inward and outward existence, has sense enough
to distinguish the mere appearance, which is transient and
meaningless, from what in itself really deserves the name of actuality. As it
is only in form that philosophy is distinguished from other modes of attaining
an acquaintance with this same sum of being, it must necessarily be in harmony
with actuality and experience. In fact, this harmony may be viewed as at least
an extrinsic means of testing the truth of a philosophy. Similarly it may be
held the highest and final aim of philosophic science to bring about, through
the ascertainment of this harmony, a reconciliation of the self-conscious
reason with the reason which is in the
world — in other words, with actuality.
In the Preface to my Philosophy of
Right, p. xix, are found the propositions:
What is
reasonable is actual
and
What is actual is reasonable.
These simple
statements have given rise to expressions of surprise and hostility, even in
quarters where it would be reckoned an insult to presume absence of philosophy,
and still more of religion. Religion at least need not be brought in evidence;
its doctrines of the divine governments of the world affirm these propositions
too decidedly. For their philosophic sense, we must presuppose intelligence
enough to know, not only that God is actual, that He is the supreme actuality,
that He alone is truly actual; but also, as regards the logical bearings of the
question, that existence is in part mere
appearance, and only in part actuality. In common life, any freak of fancy, any
error, evil and everything of the nature of evil, as well as every degenerate
and transitory existence whatever, gets in a casual way the name of actuality.
But even our ordinary feelings are enough to forbid a casual (fortuitous)
existence getting the emphatic name of an actual; for by fortuitous we mean an
existence which has no greater value than that of something possible, which may
as well not be as be. As for the term Actuality, these critics would have done
well to consider the sense in which I employ it. In a detailed Logic I had
treated among other things of actuality, and accurately distinguished it not
only from the fortuitous, which, after all, has existence, but even from the
cognate categories of existence and the other modifications of
being.
The
actuality of the rational stands opposed by the popular fancy that Ideas and
ideals are nothing but chimeras, and philosophy a mere system of such
phantasms. It is also opposed by the very different fancy that Ideas and ideals
are something far too excellent to have actuality, or something too impotent to
procure it for themselves. This divorce between idea and reality is especially
dear to the analytic understanding which
looks upon its own abstractions, dreams though they
are, as something true and real, and prides itself on the imperative ÔoughtÕ,
which it takes especial pleasure in prescribing even on the field of politics.
As if the world had waited on it to learn how it ought to be, and was not! For,
if it were as it ought to be, what would come of the precocious wisdom of that
ÔoughtÕ? When understanding turns this ÔoughtÕ against trivial external and
transitory objects, against social regulations or conditions, which very likely
possess a great relative importance for a certain time and special circles, it may
often be right. In such a case the intelligent observer may meet much that
fails to satisfy the general requirements of right; for who is not acute
enough to see a great deal in his own surroundings which is really far from
being as it ought to be? But such acuteness is mistaken in the conceit that,
when it examines these objects and pronounces what they ought to be, it is
dealing with questions of philosophic science. The object of philosophy is the Idea: and the Idea is not so
impotent as merely to have a right or an obligation to exist without actually
existing. The object of philosophy is an actuality of which those objects,
social regulations and conditions, are only the superficial outside.
¤ 7
Thus reflection — thinking things
over — in a general way involves the principle (which also means the
beginning) of philosophy. And when the reflective spirit arose again in its
independence in modern times, after the epoch of the Lutheran Reformation, it
did not, as in its beginnings among the Greeks, stand merely aloof, in a world
of its own, but at once turned its energies also upon the apparently
illimitable material of the phenomenal world. In this way the
name philosophy came to be applied to all those branches of knowledge, which
are engaged in ascertaining the standard and Universal in the ocean of
empirical individualities, as well as in ascertaining the Necessary element, or
Laws, to be found in the apparent disorder of the endless masses of the fortuitous.
It thus appears that modern philosophy derives its materials from our own
personal observations and perceptions of the external and internal world, from
nature as well as from the mind and heart of man, when both stand in the
immediate presence of the observer.
This
principle of Experience carries with it the
unspeakably important condition that, in order to accept and believe any fact,
we must be in contact with it; or, in more exact terms, that we must find the
fact united and combined with the certainty of our own selves. We must be in
touch with our subject-matter, whether it be by means of our external senses,
or, else, by our profounder mind and our intimate self-consciousness. This
principle is the same as that which has in the present day been termed faith,
immediate knowledge, the revelation in the outward world, and, above all, in
our own heart.
Those
sciences, which thus got the name of philosophy, we call empirical
sciences, for the reason that they take their departure from experience. Still
the essential results which they aim at and provide are laws, general propositions,
a theory — the thoughts of
what is found existing. On this ground the Newtonian physics was called
Natural Philosophy. Hugo Grotius, again, by putting
together and comparing the behaviour of states
towards each other as recorded in history, succeeded, with the help of the
ordinary methods of general reasoning, in laying down certain general
principles, and establishing a theory which may be termed the Philosophy of
International Law. In England this is still the usual signification of the term
philosophy. Newton continues to be celebrated as the greatest of philosophers:
and the name goes down as far as the price-lists of instrument-makers. All
instruments, such as the thermometer and barometer, which do not come under the
special head of magnetic or electric apparatus, are styled philosophical
instruments. Surely thought, and not a mere combination of wood, iron,
etc., ought to be called the instrument of philosophy! The recent science of Political Economy in particular, which in
Germany is known as Rational Economy of the State, or intelligent national
economy, has in England especially appropriated the name of philosophy.
¤ 8
In its own
field this empirical knowledge may at first give satisfaction; but in two ways
it is seen to come short. In the first place there is another circle of objects
which it does not embrace. These are Freedom, Spirit, and God. They belong to a
different sphere, not because it can be said that they have nothing to do with
experience; for though they are certainly not experiences of the senses, it is
quite an identical proposition to say that whatever is in consciousness is
experienced. The real ground for assigning them to another field of cognition
is that in their scope and content these objects evidently show
themselves as infinite.
There is an
old phrase often wrongly attributed to Aristotle, and supposed to express the
general tenor of his philosophy. Nihil est in intellectu quod non fuerit in sensu: there is
nothing in thought which has not been in sense and experience. If speculative
philosophy
refused to admit this maxim, it can only have done so from a misunderstanding.
It will, however, on the converse side no less assert: Nihil
est in sensu quod! non fuerit in intellectu. And
this may be taken in two senses. In the general sense it means that νους or spirit (the more profound idea
of νους in modern thought) is the
cause of the world. In its special meaning (see ¤ 2) it asserts that the
sentiment of right, morals, and religion is a sentiment (and in that way an
experience) of such scope and such character that it can spring from and rest
upon thought alone.
¤ 9
But in the
second place in point of form the subjective reason desires a further
satisfaction than empirical knowledge gives; and this form is, in the widest
sense of the term, Necessity (¤ 1). The method of empirical science exhibits
two defects.
The first is that the Universal or general principle
contained in it, the genus, or kind, etc., is, on its own account,
indeterminate and vague, and therefore not on its own account connected with
the Particulars or the details. Either is external and accidental to the other;
and it is the same with the particular facts which are brought into union: each
is external and accidental to the others.
The second defect is that the
beginnings are in every case data and postulates, neither accounted for nor
deduced. In both these points the form of necessity fails to get its due. Hence
reflection, whenever it sets itself to remedy these defects, becomes
speculative thinking, the thinking proper to philosophy. As a species of
reflection, therefore, which, though it has a certain community of nature with
the reflection already mentioned, is nevertheless different from it,
philosophic thought thus possesses, in addition to the common forms, some forms
of its own, of which the Notion may be taken as the
type.
The relation
of speculative science to the other sciences may be stated in the following
terms. It does not in the least neglect the empirical facts contained in the
several sciences, but recognises and adopts them: it
appreciates and applies towards its own structure the universal element in
these sciences, their laws and classifications: but besides all this, into the
categories of science it introduces, and gives currency to, other categories. The
difference, looked at in this way, is only a change of categories. Speculative
Logic contains all previous Logic and Metaphysics: it preserves the same forms
of thought, the same laws and objects — while at the same time remodelling and expanding them with wider categories.
From notion
in the speculative sense we should distinguish what is ordinarily called a
notion. The phrase, that no notion can ever comprehend the Infinite, a phrase
which has been repeated over and over again till it has grown axiomatic, is
based upon this narrow estimate of what is meant by notions.
¤ 10
This
thought, which is proposed as the instrument of philosophic knowledge, itself
calls for further explanation. We must understand in what way it possesses
necessity or cogency: and when it claims to be equal to the task of
apprehending the absolute objects (God, Spirit, Freedom), that claim must be
substantiated. Such an explanation, however, is itself a lesson in philosophy,
and properly falls within the scope of the science itself. A preliminary
attempt to make matters plain would only be unphilosophical,
and consist of a tissue of assumptions, assertions, and inferential pros and
cons, i.e. of dogmatism without cogency, as against which there would be an
equal right of counter-dogmatism.
A main line
of argument in the Critical
Philosophy
bids us pause before proceeding to inquire into God or into the true being of
things, and tells us first of all to examine the faculty of cognition and see
whether it is equal to such an effort. We ought, says Kant, to become
acquainted with the instrument, before we undertake the work for which it is to
be employed; for if the instrument be insufficient, all our trouble will be
spent in vain. The plausibility of this suggestion has won for it general
assent and admiration; the result of which has been to withdraw cognition from
an interest in its objects and absorption in the study of them, and to direct
it back upon itself; and so turn it to a question of form. Unless we wish to be
deceived by words, it is easy to see what this amounts to. In the case of other
instruments, we can try and criticise them in other
ways than by setting about the special work for which they are destined. But
the examination of knowledge can only be carried out by an act of knowledge. To
examine this so-called instrument is the same thing as to know it. But to seek
to know before we know is as absurd as the wise resolution of Scholasticus, not to venture into the water until he had
learned to swim.
Reinhold saw
the confusion with which this style of commencement is chargeable, and tried to
get out of the difficulty by starting with a hypothetical and problematical
stage of philosophising. In this way he supposed that
it would be possible, nobody can tell how, to get along, until we found
ourselves, further on, arrived at the primary truth of truths. His method, when
closely looked into, will be seen to be identical with a very common practice. It
starts from a substratum of experiential fact, or from a provisional assumption
which has been brought into a definition; and then proceeds to analyse this starting-point. We can detect in ReinholdÕs
argument a perception of the truth, that the usual course which proceeds by
assumptions and anticipations is no better than a hypothetical and
problematical mode of procedure. But his perceiving this does not alter the
character of this method; it only makes clear its imperfections.
¤ 11
The special
conditions which call for the existence of philosophy may be thus described.
The mind or spirit, when it is sentient or perceptive, finds its object in
something sensuous; when it imagines, in a picture or image; when it wills, in
an aim or end. But in contrast to, or it may be only in distinction from, these
forms of its existence and of its objects, the mind has also to gratify the
cravings of its highest and most inward life. That innermost self is thought.
Thus the mind renders thought its object. In the best meaning of the phrase, it
comes to itself; for thought is its principle, and its very unadulterated self.
But while thus occupied, thought entangles itself in contradictions, i.e. loses itself in
the hard-and-fast non-identity of its thoughts, and so, instead of reaching
itself, is caught and held in its counterpart. This result, to which honest but
narrow thinking leads the mere understanding, is resisted by the loftier craving
of which we have spoken. That craving expresses the perseverance of thought,
which continues true to itself, even in this conscious loss of its native rest
and independence, Ôthat it may overcomeÕ and work out in itself the solution of
its own contradictions.
To see that
thought in its very nature is dialectical, and that, as understanding, it must fall into
contradiction — the negative of itself — will form one of the main
lessons of logic. When thought grows hopeless of ever achieving, by its own
means, the solution of the contradiction which it has by its own action brought
upon itself, it turns back to those solutions of the question with which the
mind had learned to pacify itself in some of its other modes and forms.
Unfortunately, however, the retreat of thought has led it, as Plato noticed
even in his time, to a very uncalled-for hatred of reason (misology); and it
then takes up against its own endeavours that hostile
attitude of which an example is seen in the doctrine that ÔimmediateÕ
knowledge, as it is called, is the exclusive form in which we become cognisant of truth.
¤ 12
The rise of
philosophy is due to these cravings of thought. Its point of departure is
Experience; including under that name both our immediate consciousness and the inductions from it. Awakened, as
it were, by this stimulus, thought is vitally characterised
by raising itself above the natural state of mind, above the senses and
inferences from the senses into its own unadulterated element, and by assuming,
accordingly, at first a stand-aloof and negative attitude towards the
point from which it started. Through this state of antagonism to the phenomena
of sense its first satisfaction is found in itself, in the Idea of the
universal essence of these phenomena: an Idea (the Absolute, or God) which may be
more or less abstract. Meanwhile, on the other hand, the sciences, based on
experience, exert upon the mind a stimulus to overcome the form in which their
varied contents are presented, and to elevate these contents to the rank of
necessary truth. For the facts of science have the aspect of a vast
conglomerate, one thing coming side by side with another, as if they were
merely given and presented — as in short devoid of all essential or
necessary connection. In consequence of this stimulus, thought is dragged out
of its unrealised universality and its fancied or
merely possible satisfaction, and impelled onwards to a development from
itself. On one hand this development only means that thought incorporates the
contents of science, in all their speciality of
detail as submitted. On the other it makes these contents imitate the action of
the original creative thought, and present the aspect of a free evolution
determined by the logic of the fact alone.
On the
relation between ÔimmediacyÕ and ÔmediationÕ in consciousness we shall
speak later, expressly and with more detail. Here it may be sufficient to
premise that, though the two ÔmomentsÕ or factors present themselves as
distinct, still neither of them can be absent, nor can one exist apart from the
other. Thus the knowledge of God, as of every supersensible reality, is in its
true character an exaltation above sensations or perceptions: it consequently
involves a negative attitude to the initial data of sense, and to that extent
implies mediation. For to mediate is to take something as a beginning and to go
onward to a second thing; so that the existence of this second thing depends on
our having reached it from something else contradistinguished from it. In spite
of this, the knowledge of God is no mere sequel, dependent on the empirical
phase of consciousness: in fact, its independence is essentially secured
through this negation and exaltation. No doubt, if we attach an unfair
prominence to the fact of mediation, and represent it as implying a state of conditionedness, it may be said — not that the remark
would mean much — that philosophy is the child of experience, and owes
its rise to a posteriori fact. (As a matter of fact, thinking is always
the negation of what we have immediately before us.) With as much truth however
we may be said to owe eating to the means of nourishment, so long as we can
have no eating without them. If we take this view, eating is certainly
represented as ungrateful: it devours that to which it owes itself. Thinking,
upon this view of its action, is equally ungrateful.
But there is
also an a priori aspect of thought, where by a mediation, not made by
anything external but by a reflection into self, we have that immediacy which
is universality, the selfcomplacency of thought which
is so much at home with itself that it feels an innate indifference to descend
to particulars, and in that way to the development of its own nature. It is
thus also with religion, which whether it be rude or elaborate, whether it be
invested with scientific precision of detail or confined to the simple faith of
the heart, possesses, throughout, the same intensive nature of contentment and
felicity. But if thought never gets further than the universality of the Ideas,
as was perforce the case in the first philosophies (when the Eleatics never got beyond Being, or Heraclitus beyond
Becoming), it is justly open to the charge of formalism. Even in a more
advanced phase of philosophy, we may often find a doctrine which has mastered
merely certain abstract propositions or formulae, such as, ÔIn the absolute all
is oneÕ, ÔSubject and object are identicalÕ — and only repeating the same
thing when it comes to particulars. Bearing in mind this first period of
thought, the period of mere generality, we may safely say that experience is
the real author of growth and advance in
philosophy. For, firstly, the empirical sciences do not stop short at the mere
observation of the individual features of a phenomenon. By the aid of thought,
they are able to meet philosophy with materials prepared for it, in the shape
of general uniformities, i.e. laws, and classifications of the phenomena. When
this is done, the particular facts which they contain are ready to be received
into philosophy. This, secondly, implies a certain compulsion on thought itself
to proceed to these concrete specific truths. The reception into philosophy of
these scientific materials, now that thought has removed their immediacy and
made them cease to be mere data, forms at the same time a development of
thought out of itself. Philosophy, then, owes its development to the empirical
sciences. In return it gives their contents what is so vital to them, the
freedom of thought — gives them, in short, an a priori character.
These contents are now warranted necessary, and no longer depend on the
evidence of facts merely, that they were so found and so experienced. The fact
as experienced thus becomes an illustration and a copy of the original and
completely self-supporting activity of thought.
¤ 13
Stated in
exact terms, such is the origin and development of philosophy. But the History
of Philosophy gives us the same process from a historical and external point of
view. The stages in the evolution of the Idea there seem to follow each other
by accident, and to present merely a number of different and unconnected
principles, which the several systems of philosophy carry out in their own way.
But it is not so. For these thousands of years the same Architect has directed
the work: and that Architect is the one living Mind whose nature is to think,
to bring to self-consciousness what it is, and, with its being thus set as
object before it, to be at the same time raised above it, and so to reach a
higher stage of its own being. The different systems which the history of
philosophy presents are therefore not irreconcilable with unity.
We may
either say, that it is one philosophy at different degrees of maturity: or that
the particular principle, which is the groundwork of each system, is but a
branch of one and the same universe of thought. In philosophy the latest birth
of time is the result of all the systems that have preceded it, and must
include their principles; and so, if, on other grounds, it deserve the title of
philosophy, will be the fullest, most comprehensive, and most adequate system
of all.
The
spectacle of so many and so various systems of philosophy suggests the
necessity of defining more exactly the relation of Universal to Particular. When the universal is
made a mere form and co-ordinated with the
particular, as if it were on the same level, it sinks into a particular itself.
Even common sense in everyday matters is above the absurdity of setting a
universal beside the particulars. Would any one, who wished for
fruit, reject cherries, pears, and grapes, on the ground that they were
cherries, pears, or grapes, and not fruit? But when philosophy is in question,
the excuse of many is that philosophies are so different, and none of them is
the philosophy — that each is only a philosophy. Such a plea is assumed
to justify any amount of contempt for philosophy. And yet cherries too are
fruit. Often, too, a system, of which the principle is the universal, is put on
a level with another of which the principle is a particular, and with theories
which deny the existence of philosophy altogether. Such systems are said to be
only different views of philosophy. With equal justice, light and darkness
might be styled different kinds of light.
¤ 14
The same
evolution of thought which is exhibited in the history of philosophy is
presented in the System of Philosophy itself.
Here, instead of surveying the process, as we do in history, from the outside,
we see the movement of thought clearly defined in its native medium. The thought,
which is genuine and self-supporting, must be intrinsically concrete; it must
be an Idea; and when it is viewed in the whole of its universality, it is the
Idea, or the Absolute. The science of this Idea must form a system. For the
truth is concrete; that is, while it gives a bond and principle of unity, it
also possesses an internal source of development. Truth, then, is only possible
as a universe or totality of thought; and the freedom of the whole, as well as
the necessity of the several
sub-divisions,
which it implies, are only possible when these are discriminated and defined.
Unless it is
a system, a philosophy is not a scientific production. Unsystematic philosophising can only be expected to give expression to
personal peculiarities of mind, and has no principle for the regulation of its
contents. Apart from their interdependence and organic union, the truths of
philosophy are valueless, and must then be treated as baseless hypotheses, or
personal convictions. Yet many philosophical treatises confine themselves to
such an exposition of the opinions and sentiments of the author.
The term
system is often misunderstood. It does not denote a philosophy, the principle
of which is narrow and to be distinguished from others. On the contrary, a
genuine philosophy makes it a principle to include every particular principle.
¤ 15
Each of
the parts of philosophy is a philosophical whole, a circle rounded and complete
in itself.
In each of these parts, however, the philosophical Idea is found in a
particular specificality or medium. The single
circle, because it is a real totality, bursts through the limits imposed by its
special medium, and gives rise to a wider circle. The whole of philosophy in
this way resembles a circle of circles. The Idea appears in each single
circle, but, at the same time, the whole Idea is constituted by the system of
these peculiar phases, and each is a necessary member of the organisation.
¤ 16
In the form
of an Encyclopaedia, the science has no room for a
detailed exposition of particulars, and must be limited to setting forth the
commencement of the special sciences and the notions of cardinal importance in
them.
How much of
the particular parts is requisite to constitute a particular branch of
knowledge is so far indeterminate, that the part, if it is to be something
true, must be not an isolated member merely, but itself an organic whole. The
entire field of philosophy therefore really forms a single science; but it may
also be viewed as a total, composed of several particular sciences.
The encyclopaedia of philosophy must not be confounded with
ordinary encyclopaedias. An ordinary encyclopaedia does not pretend to be more than an
aggregation of sciences, regulated by no principle, and merely as experience
offers them. Sometimes it even includes what merely bear the name of sciences,
while they are nothing more than a collection of bits of information. In an
aggregate like this, the several branches of knowledge owe their place in the encyclopaedia to extrinsic reasons, and their unity is
therefore artificial: they are arranged, but we cannot say they
form a system. For the same reason, especially as the materials
to be combined also depend upon no one rule or principle, the arrangement is at
best an experiment, and will always exhibit inequalities.
An encyclopaedia of philosophy excludes three kinds of partial
science. I. It excludes mere aggregates of bits of
information. Philology in its prima facie aspect belongs to this class. II. It rejects the quasi-sciences, which are founded on an act
of arbitrary will alone, such as Heraldry. Sciences of this class are positive from beginning to end. III. In another class of sciences, also styled positive, but
which have a rational basis and a rational beginning, philosophy claims that
constituent as its own. The positive features remain the property of the
sciences themselves.
The positive
element in the last class of sciences is of different sorts. (i) Their commencement,
though rational at bottom, yields to the influence of fortuitousness, when they
have to bring their universal truth into contact with actual facts and the
single phenomena of experience. In this region of chance and change, the
adequate notion of science must yield its place to reasons or grounds of
explanation. Thus, e.g. in the science of jurisprudence, or in the system of
direct and indirect taxation, it is necessary to have certain points precisely
and definitively settled which lie beyond the competence of the absolute lines
laid down by the pure notion. A certain latitude of settlement accordingly is
left; and each point may be determined in one way on one principle, in another
way on another, and admits of no definitive certainty. Similarly the Idea of Nature, when parcelled out in detail, is dissipated into contingencies.
Natural history, geography, and medicine stumble upon descriptions of
existence, upon kinds and distinctions, which are not determined by reason, but
by sport and adventitious incidents. Even history comes under the same
category. The Idea is its essence and inner nature; but, as it appears,
everything is under contingency and in the field of voluntary action. (ii) These sciences are positive also in failing to recognise the finite nature of what they predicate, and to
point out how these categories and their whole sphere pass into a higher. They
assume their statements to possess an authority beyond appeal. Here the fault
lies in the finitude of the form, as in the previous instance it lay in the
matter. (iii) In close sequel to
this, sciences are positive in consequence of the inadequate grounds on which
their conclusions rest: based as these are on detached and casual inference,
upon feeling, faith, and authority, and, generally speaking, upon the
deliverances of inward and outward perception. Under this head we must also
class the philosophy which proposes to build upon ÔanthropologyÕ, facts of
consciousness, inward sense, or outward experience. It may happen, however,
that empirical is an epithet applicable only to the form of scientific
exposition, while intuitive sagacity has arranged what are mere phenomena,
according to the essential sequence of the notion. In such a case the contrasts
between the varied and numerous phenomena brought together serve to eliminate
the external and accidental circumstances of their conditions, and the
universal thus comes clearly into view. Guided by such an intuition,
experimental physics will present the rational science of Nature — as
history will present the science of human affairs and actions — in an
external picture, which mirrors the philosophic notion.
¤ 17
It may seem
as if philosophy, in order to start on its course, had, like the rest of the
sciences, to begin with a subjective presupposition. The sciences postulate
their respective objects, such as space, number, or whatever it be; and it
might be supposed that philosophy had also to postulate the existence of
thought. But the two cases are not exactly parallel. It is by the free act of
thought that it occupies a point of view, in which it is for its own self, and
thus gives itself an object of its own production. Nor is this all. The very
point of view, which originally is taken on its own evidence only, must in the
course of the science be converted to a result — the ultimate result in
which philosophy returns into itself and reaches the point with which it began.
In this manner philosophy exhibits the appearance of a circle which closes with
itself, and has no beginning in the same way as the other sciences have. To
speak of a beginning of philosophy has a meaning only in relation to a person
who proposes to commence the study, and not in relation to the science as
science. The same thing may be thus expressed. The notion of science —
the notion therefore with which we start — which, for the very reason
that it is initial, implies a separation between the thought which is our
object, and the subject philosophising which is, as
it were, external to the former, must be grasped and comprehended by the
science itself. This is in short, the one single aim, action, and goal of
philosophy — to arrive at the notion of its notion, and thus secure its
return and its satisfaction.
¤ 18
As the whole
science, and only the whole, can exhibit what the Idea or system of reason is,
it is impossible to give in a preliminary way a general impression of a
philosophy. Nor can a division of philosophy into its parts be intelligible,
except in connection with the system. A preliminary division, like the limited
conception from which it comes, can only be an anticipation. Here however it is
premised that the Idea turns out to be the thought which is completely
identical with itself, and not identical simply in the abstract, but also in
its action of setting itself over against itself, so as to gain a being of its
own, and yet of being in full possession of itself while it is in this other.
Thus philosophy is subdivided into three parts:
I. Logic: the science of the
Idea in and for itself.
II. The Philosophy of
Nature:
the science of the Idea in its otherness.
III. The Philosophy of Mind: the science of the
Idea come back to itself out of that otherness.
As observed in ¤15, the differences between the
several philosophical sciences are only aspects or specialisations
of the one Idea or system of reason, which and which alone is alike exhibited
in these different media. In Nature nothing else would have to be discerned,
except the Idea; but the Idea has here divested itself of its proper being. In
Mind, again, the Idea has asserted a being of its own, and is on the way to
become absolute. Every such form in which the Idea is expressed is at the same
time a passing or fleeting stage; and hence each of these subdivisions has not
only to know its contents as an object which has being for the time, but also
in the same act to expound how these contents pass into their higher circle. To
represent the relation between them as a division, therefore, leads to
misconception; for it co-ordinates the several parts or sciences one beside
another, as if they had no innate development, but were, like so many species,
really and radically distinct.