Selections from On the Aesthetic Education of Man (Fredrich Schiller, 1794)
...
If
we bestow some serious attention to the character of our times, we
shall be astonished at the contrast between the present and the
previous form of humanity, especially that of Greece. We are justified
in claiming the reputation of culture and refinement, when contrasted
with a purely natural state of society, but not so comparing ourselves
with the Grecian nature. For the latter was combined with all the
charms of art and with all the dignity of wisdom, without, however, as
with us, becoming a victim to these influences. The Greeks put us to
shame not only by their simplicity, which is foreign to our age; they
are at the same time our rivals, nay, frequently our models, in those
very points of superiority from which we seek comfort when regretting
the unnatural character of our manners. We see that remarkable people
uniting at once fulness of form and fulness of substance, both
philosophising and creating, both tender and energetic, uniting a
youthful fancy to the virility of reason in a glorious humanity.
At
the period of Greek culture, which was an awakening of the powers of
the mind, the senses and the spirit had no distinctly separated
property; no division had yet torn them asunder, leading them to
partition in a hostile attitude, and to mark off their limits with
precision. Poetry had not yet become the adversary of wit, nor had
speculation abused itself by passing into quibbling. In cases of
necessity both poetry and wit could exchange parts, because they both
honoured truth only in their special way. However high might be the
flight of reason, it drew matter in a loving spirit after it, and,
while sharply and stiffly defining it, never mutilated what it touched.
It is true the Greek mind displaced humanity, and recast it on a
magnified scale in the glorious circle of its gods; but it did this not
by dissecting human nature, but by giving it fresh combinations, for
the whole of human nature was represented in each of the gods. How
different is the course followed by us moderns! We also displace and
magnify individuals to form the image of the species, but we do this in
a fragmentary way, not by altered combinations, so that it is necessary
to gather up from different individuals the elements that form the
species in its totality. It would almost appear as if the powers of
mind express themselves with us in real life or empirically as
separately as the psychologist distinguishes them in the
representation. For we see not only individual subjects, but whole
classes of men, uphold their capacities only in part, while the rest of
their faculties scarcely show a germ of activity, as in the case of the
stunted growth of plants.
I
do not overlook the advantages to which the present race, regarded as a
unity and in the balance of the understanding, may lay claim over what
is best in the ancient world; but it is obliged to engage in the
contest as a compact mass, and measure itself as a whole against a
whole. Who among the moderns could step forth, man against man, and
strive with an Athenian for the prize of higher humanity?
Whence
comes this disadvantageous relation of individuals coupled with great
advantages of the race? Why could the individual Greek be qualified as
the type of his time? and why can no modern dare to offer himself as
such? Because all-uniting nature imparted its forms to the Greek, and
an all-dividing understanding gives our forms to us.
It
was culture itself that gave these wounds to modern humanity. The inner
union of human nature was broken, and a destructive contest divided its
harmonious forces directly; on the one hand, an enlarged experience and
a more distinct thinking necessitated a sharper separation of the
sciences, while on the other hand, the more complicated machinery of
states necessitated a stricter sundering of ranks and occupations.
Intuitive and speculative understanding took up a hostile attitude in
opposite fields, whose borders were guarded with jealousy and distrust;
and by limiting its operation to a narrow sphere, men have made unto
themselves a master who is wont not unfrequently to end by subduing and
oppressing all the other faculties. Whilst on the one hand a luxuriant
imagination creates ravages in the plantations that have cost the
intelligence so much labour, on the other hand a spirit of abstraction
suffocates the fire that might have warmed the heart and inflamed the
imagination.
This
subversion, commenced by art and learning in the inner man, was carried
out to fullness and finished by the spirit of innovation in government.
It was, no doubt, reasonable to expect that the simple organisation of
the primitive republics should survive the quaintness of primitive
manners and of the relations of antiquity. But, instead of rising to a
higher and nobler degree of animal life, this organisation degenerated
into a common and coarse mechanism. The zoophyte condition of the
Grecian states, where each individual enjoyed an independent life, and
could, in cases of necessity, become a separate whole and unit in
himself, gave way to an ingenious mechanism, whence, from the splitting
up into numberless parts, there results a mechanical life in the
combination. Then there was a rupture between the state and the church,
between laws and customs; enjoyment was separated from labour, the
means from the end, the effort from the reward. Man himself eternally
chained down to a little fragment of the whole, only forms a kind of
fragment; having nothing in his ears but the monotonous sound of the
perpetually revolving wheel, he never develops the harmony of his
being; and instead of imprinting the seal of humanity on his being, he
ends by being nothing more than the living impress of the craft to
which he devotes himself, of the science that he cultivates.
...
My
subject has led me naturally to place in relief the distressing
tendency of the character of our own times to show the sources of the
evil, without its being my province to point out the compensations
offered by nature. I will readily admit to you that, although this
splitting up of their being was unfavourable for individuals, it was
the only road open for the progress of the race. The point at which we
see humanity arrived among the Greeks was undoubtedly a maximum; it
could neither stop there nor rise higher. It could not stop there, for
the sum of notions acquired forced infallibly the intelligence to break
with feeling and intuition, and to lead to clearness of knowledge. Nor
could it rise any higher; for it is only in a determinate measure that
clearness can be reconciled with a certain degree of abundance and of
warmth. The Greeks had attained this measure, and to continue their
progress in culture, they, as we, were obliged to renounce the totality
of their being, and to follow different and separate roads in order to
seek after truth.
There
was no other way to develop the manifold aptitudes of man than to bring
them in opposition with one another. This antagonism of forces is the
great instrument of culture, but it is only an instrument; for as long
as this antagonism lasts, man is only on the road to culture.
...
The
object of the sensuous instinct, expressed in a universal conception,
is named Life in the widest acceptation: a conception that expresses
all material existence and all that is immediately present in the
senses. The object of the formal instinct, expressed in a universal
conception, is called shape or form, as well in an exact as in an
inexact acceptation; a conception that embraces all formal qualities of
things and all relations of the same to the thinking powers. The object
of the play instinct, represented in a general statement, may therefore
bear the name of living form; a term that serves to describe all
aesthetic qualities of phaenomena, and what people style, in the widest
sense, beauty.
Beauty
is neither extended to the whole field of all living things nor merely
enclosed in this field. A marble block, though it is and remains
lifeless, can nevertheless become a living form by the architect and
sculptor; a man, though he lives and has a form, is far from being a
living form on that account. For this to be the case, it is necessary
that his form should be life, and that his life should be a form. As
long as we only think of his form, it is lifeless, a mere abstraction;
as long as we only feel his life, it is without form, a mere
impression. It is only when his form lives in our feeling, and his life
in our understanding, he is the living form, and this will everywhere
be the case where we judge him to be beautiful.
But
the genesis of beauty is by no means declared because we know how to
point out the component parts, which in their combination produce
beauty. For to this end it would be necessary to comprehend that
combination itself, which continues to defy our exploration, as well as
all mutual operation between the finite and the infinite. The reason,
on transcendental grounds, makes the following demand: There shall be a
communion between the formal impulse and the material impulse - that
is, there shall be a play instinct - because it is only the unity of
reality with the form, of the accidental with the necessary, of the
passive state with freedom, that the conception of humanity is
completed.
...
We
know that man is neither exclusively matter nor exclusively spirit.
Accordingly, beauty, as the consummation of humanity, can neither be
exclusively mere life, as has been asserted by sharp-sighted observers,
who kept too close to the testimony of experience, and to which the
taste of the time would gladly degrade it; Nor can beauty be merely
form, as has been judged by speculative sophists, who departed too far
from experience, and by philosophic artists, who were led too much by
the necessity of art in explaining beauty; it is rather the common
object of both impulses, that is, of the play instinct. The use of
language completely justifies this name, as it is wont to qualify with
the word play what is neither subjectively nor objectively accidental,
and yet does not impose necessity either externally or internally. As
the mind in the intuition of the beautiful finds itself in a happy
medium between law and necessity, it is, because it divides itself
between both, emancipated from the pressure of both.
...
But
perhaps the objection has for some time occurred to you, Is not the
beautiful degraded by this, that it is made a mere play? and is it not
reduced to the level of frivolous objects which have for ages passed
under that name? Does it not contradict the conception of the reason
and the dignity of beauty, which is nevertheless regarded as an
instrument of culture, to confine it to the work of being a mere play?
and does it not contradict the empirical conception of play, which can
coexist with the exclusion of all taste, to confine it merely to
beauty?
But
what is meant by a mere play, when we know that in all conditions of
humanity that very thing is play, and only that is play which makes man
complete and develops simultaneously his twofold nature? What you style
limitation, according to your representation of the matter, according
to my views, which I have justified by proofs, I name enlargement.
Consequently, I should have said exactly the reverse: man is serious
only with the agreeable, with the good, and with the perfect, but he
plays with beauty. In saying this we must not indeed think of the plays
that are in vogue in real life, and which commonly refer only to his
material state. But in real life we should also seek in vain for the
beauty of which we are here speaking. The actually present beauty is
worthy of the really, of the actually, present play- impulse; but by
the ideal of beauty, which is set up by the reason, an ideal of the
play-instinct is also presented, which man ought to have before his
eyes in all his plays.
Therefore,
no error will ever be incurred if we seek the ideal of beauty on the
same road on which we satisfy our play-impulse. We can immediately
understand why the ideal form of a Venus, of a Juno, and of an Apollo,
is to be sought not at Rome, but in Greece, if we contrast the Greek
population, delighting in the bloodless athletic contests of boxing,
racing, and intellectual rivalry at Olympia, with the Roman people
gloating over the agony of a gladiator. Now the reason pronounces that
the beautiful must not only be life and form, but a living form, that
is, beauty, inasmuch as it dictates to man the twofold law of absolute
formality and absolute reality. Reason also utters the decision that
man shall only play with beauty, and he shall only play with beauty.
For,
to speak out once for all, man only plays when in the full meaning of
the word he is a man, and he is only completely a man when he plays.
This proposition, which at this moment perhaps appears paradoxical,
will receive a great and deep meaning if we have advanced far enough to
apply it to the twofold seriousness of duty and of destiny. I promise
you that the whole edifice of aesthetic art and the still more
difficult art of life will be supported by this principle.
...
No
doubt nature has given more than is necessary to unreasoning beings;
she has caused a gleam of freedom to shine even in the darkness of
animal life. When the lion is not tormented by hunger, and when no wild
beast challenges him to fight, his unemployed energy creates an object
for himself; full of ardour, he fills the re-echoing desert with his
terrible roars, and his exuberant force rejoices in itself, showing
itself without an object. The insect flits about rejoicing in life in
the sunlight, and it is certainly not the cry of want that makes itself
heard in the melodious song of the bird; there is undeniably freedom in
these movements, though it is not emancipation from want in general,
but from a determinate external necessity.
The
animal works, when a privation is the motor of its activity, and it
plays when the plenitude of force is this motor, when an exuberant life
is excited to action. Even in inanimate nature a luxury of strength and
a latitude of determination are shown, which in this material sense
might be styled play. The tree produces numberless germs that are
abortive without developing, and it sends forth more roots, branches
and leaves, organs of nutrition, than are used for the preservation of
the species. Whatever this tree restores to the elements of its
exuberant life, without using it, or enjoying it, may be expended by
life in free and joyful movements. It is thus that nature offers in her
material sphere a sort of prelude to the limitless, and that even there
she suppresses partially the chains from which she will be completely
emancipated in the realm of form. The constraint of superabundance or
physical play, answers as a transition from the constraint of
necessity, or of physical seriousness, to aesthetical play; and before
shaking off, in the supreme freedom of the beautiful, the yoke of any
special aim, nature already approaches, at least remotely, this
independence, by the free movement which is itself its own end and
means.
The
imagination, like the bodily organs, has in man its free movement and
its material play, a play in which, without any reference to form, it
simply takes pleasure in its arbitrary power and in the absence of all
hindrance. These plays of fancy, inasmuch as form is not mixed up with
them, and because a free succession of images makes all their charm,
though confined to man, belong exclusively to animal life, and only
prove one thing - that he is delivered from all external sensuous
constraint - without our being entitled to infer that there is in it an
independent plastic force.
From
this play of free association of ideas, which is still quite material
in nature and is explained by simple natural laws, the imagination, by
making the attempt of creating a free form, passes at length at a jump
to the aesthetic play: I say at one leap, for quite a new force enters
into action here; for here, for the first time, the legislative mind is
mixed with the acts of a blind instinct, subjects the arbitrary march
of the imagination to its eternal and immutable unity, causes its
independent permanence to enter in that which is transitory, and its
infinity in the sensuous. Nevertheless, as long as rude nature, which
knows of no other law than running incessantly from change to change,
will yet retain too much strength, it will oppose itself by its
different caprices to this necessity; by its agitation to this
permanence; by its manifold needs to this independence, and by its
insatiability to this sublime simplicity. It will be also troublesome
to recognise the instinct of play in its first trials, seeing that the
sensuous impulsion, with its capricious humour and its violent
appetites, constantly crosses. It is on that account that we see the
taste, still coarse, seize that which is new and startling, the
disordered, the adventurous and the strange, the violent and the
savage, and fly from nothing so much as from calm and simplicity. It
invents grotesque figures, it likes rapid transitions, luxurious forms,
sharply marked changes, acute tones, a pathetic song. That which man
calls beautiful at this time, is that which excites him, that which
gives him matter; but that which excites him to give his personality to
the object, that which gives matter to a possible plastic operation,
for otherwise it would not be the beautiful for him. A remarkable
change has therefore taken place in form of his judgments; he searches
for these objects, not because they affect him, but because they
furnish him with the occasion of acting; they please him, not because
they answer to a want, but because they satisfy a law, which speaks in
his breast, although quite low as yet.
Soon
it will not be sufficient for things to please him; he will wish to
please: in the first place, it is true, only by that which belongs to
him; afterwards by that which he is. That which he possesses, that
which he produces, ought not merely to bear any more the traces of
servitude, nor to mark out the end, simply and scrupulously, by the
form. Independently of the use to which it is destined, the object
ought also to reflect the enlightened intelligence which imagines it,
the hand which shaped it with affection, the mind free and serene which
chose it and exposed it to view. Now, the ancient German searches for
more magnificent furs, for more splendid antlers of the stag, for more
elegant drinking horns; and the Caledonian chooses the prettiest shells
for his festivals. The arms themselves ought to be no longer only
objects of terror, but also of pleasure; and the skilfully worked
scabbard will not attract less attention than the homicidal edge of the
sword. The instinct of play, not satisfied with bringing into the
sphere of the necessary an aesthetic superabundance for the future more
free, is at last completely emancipated from the bonds of duty, and the
beautiful becomes of itself an object of man`s exertions. He adorns
himself. The free pleasure comes to take a place among his wants, and
the useless soon becomes the best part of his joys. Form, which from
the outside gradually approaches him, in his dwellings, his furniture,
his clothing, begins at last to take possession of the man himself, to
transform him, at first exteriorly, and afterwards in the interior. The
disordered leaps of joy become the dance, the formless gesture is
changed into an amiable and harmonious pantomime, the confused accents
of feeling are developed, and begin to obey measure and adapt
themselves to song. When, like the flight of cranes, the Trojan army
rushes on to the field of battle with thrilling cries, the Greek army
approaches in silence and with a noble and measured step. On the one
side we see but the exuberance of a blind force, on the other the
triumph of form and the simple majesty of law.
Now,
a nobler necessity binds the two sexes mutually, and the interests of
the heart contribute in rendering durable an alliance which was at
first capricious and changing like the desire that knits it. Delivered
from the heavy fetters of desire, the eye, now calmer, attends to the
form, the soul contemplates the soul, and the interested exchange of
pleasure becomes a generous exchange of mutual inclination. Desire
enlarges and rises to love, in proportion as it sees humanity dawn in
its object; and, despising the vile triumphs gained by the senses, man
tries to win a nobler victory over the will. The necessity of pleasing
subjects the powerful nature to the gentle laws of taste; pleasure may
be stolen, but love must be a gift. To obtain this higher recompense,
it is only through the form and not through matter that it can carry on
the contest. It must cease to act on feeling as a force, to appear in
the intelligence as a simple phaenomenon; it must respect liberty, as
it is liberty it wishes to please. The beautiful reconciles the
contrast of different natures in its simplest and purest expression. It
also reconciles the eternal contrast of the two sexes, in the whole
complex framework of society, or at all events it seeks to do so; and,
taking as its model the free alliance it has knit between manly
strength and womanly gentleness, it strives to place in harmony, in the
moral world, all the elements of gentleness and of violence. Now, at
length, weakness becomes sacred, and an unbridled strength disgraces;
the injustice of nature is corrected by the generosity of chivalrous
manners. The being whom no power can make tremble, is disarmed by the
amiable blush of modesty, and tears extinguish a vengeance that blood
could not have quenched. Hatred itself hears the delicate voice of
honour, the conqueror`s sword spares the disarmed enemy, and a
hospitable hearth smokes for the stranger on the dreaded hill-side
where murder alone awaited him before.
In
the midst of the formidable realm of forces, and of the sacred empire
of laws, the aesthetic impulse of form creates by degrees a third and a
joyous realm, that of play and of the appearance, where she emancipates
man from fetters, in all his relations, an from all that is named
constraint, whether physical or moral.
If
in the dynamic state of rights men mutually move and come into
collision as forces, in the moral (ethical) state of duties, man
opposes to man the majesty of the laws, and chains down his will. In
this realm of the beautiful or the aesthetic state, man ought to appear
to man only as a form, and an object of free play. To give freedom
through freedom is the fundamental law of this realm.
The
dynamic state can only make society simply possible by subduing nature
through nature; the moral (ethical) state can only make it morally
necessary by submitting the will of the individual to the general will.
The aesthetic state alone can make it real, because it carries out the
will of all through the nature of the individual. If necessity alone
forces man to enter into society, and if this reason engraves on his
soul social principles, it is beauty only that can give him a social
character; taste alone brings harmony into society, because it creates
harmony in the individual. All other forms of perception divide the
man, because they are based exclusively either in the sensuous or in
the spiritual part of his being. It is only the perception of beauty
that makes of him an entirety, because it demands the co-operation of
his two natures. All other forms of communication divide society,
because they apply exclusively either to the receptivity or to the
private activity of its members, and therefore to what distinguishes
men one from the other. The aesthetic communication alone unites
society, because it applies to what is common to all its members. We
only enjoy the pleasures of sense as individuals, without the nature of
the race in us sharing in it; accordingly, we cannot generalise our
individual pleasures, because we cannot generalise our individuality.
We enjoy the pleasures of knowledge as a race, dropping the individual
in our judgment; but we cannot generalise the pleasures of the
understanding, because we cannot eliminate individuality from the
judgments of others as we do from our own. Beauty alone can we enjoy
both as individuals and as a race, that is, as representing a race.
Good appertaining to sense can only make one person happy, because it
is founded on inclination, which is always exclusive; and it can only
make a man partially happy, because his real personality does not share
in it. Absolute good can only render a man happy conditionally, for
truth is only the reward of abnegation, and a pure heart alone has
faith in a pure will. Beauty alone confers happiness on all, and under
its influence every being forgets that he is limited.
...